Cover of Philo
Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Browse by:



Displaying: 1-19 of 19 documents


editorial
1. Philo: Volume > 2 > Issue: 2
Keith M. Parsons The Big Issues
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
papers
2. Philo: Volume > 2 > Issue: 2
Douglas Walton Can an Ancient Argument of Carneades on Cardinal Virtues and Divine Attributes be Used to Disprove the Existence of God?
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
An ancient argument attributed to the philosopher Carneades is presented that raises critical questions about the concept of an all-virtuous Divine being. The argument is based on the premises that virtue involves overcoming pains and dangers, and that only a being that can suffer or be destroyed is one for whom there are pains and dangers. The conclusion is that an all-virtuous Divine (perfect) being cannot exist. After presenting this argument, reconstructed from sources in Sextus Empiricus and Cicero, this paper goes on to model it as a deductively valid sequence of reasoning. The paper also discusses whet her the premises are true. Questions about the possibility and value of proving and disproving the existence of God by logical reasoning are raised, as well as ethical questions about how the cardinal ethical virtues should be defined.
3. Philo: Volume > 2 > Issue: 2
R. Harwood Dying for It
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
The claim that the Resurrection of Jesus is historical fact is often justified on the basis that the disciples died for the belief. I analyze the argument, and show that three key premises cannot be accepted. The first is the claim that the disciples died for their beliefs. I give a detailed analysis of what is involved in dying for a belief in this context, and show that we have no assurance that the disciples died for their beliefs in that sense at all. The second is that the disciples could not have been sincerely mistaken, and the third is that the beliefs of the disciples were those attributed to them by apologists. I suggest that neither of these premises can be established with any certainty.
4. Philo: Volume > 2 > Issue: 2
John Beaudoin On Some Criticisms of Hume’s Principle of Proportioning Cause to Effect
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
That no qualities ought to be ascribed to a cause beyond what are requisite for bringing about its effect(s) is a methodological principle Hume employs to evacuate arguments from design of much theological significance. In this article I defend Hume’s use of the principle against several objections brought against it by Richard Swinburne.
5. Philo: Volume > 2 > Issue: 2
Eric Sotnak The Kalam Cosmological Argument and the Possibility of an Actually Infinite Future
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Part of the kalam cosmological argument draws upon the claim that an actual infinite cannot exist. Classical theists also maintain both that some individuals will earn eternal life and that God infallibly foreknows the future. The claim that these latter two theses do not require that an actual infinite exists because God possesses an intuitive, rather than propositional intellect, is examined and rejected. Although the future is potential, rather than actual, classical theism requires that the future be, in a sense, actually infinite.
6. Philo: Volume > 2 > Issue: 2
Paul Edwards Richard Swinburne’s Arguments
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
book reviews
7. Philo: Volume > 2 > Issue: 2
Basil Smith Defending Theistic Proofs
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
8. Philo: Volume > 2 > Issue: 2
Peter Hutcheson Another Way Between Atheism and Theism?
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
9. Philo: Volume > 2 > Issue: 2
Antony Flew Explaining the Resurrection
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
10. Philo: Volume > 2 > Issue: 2
Austin Dacey Swinburne’s Ultimate Explanation
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
editorial
11. Philo: Volume > 2 > Issue: 1
Keith M. Parsons Uncovering the Other Side of the Debate
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
papers
12. Philo: Volume > 2 > Issue: 1
Wes Morriston Must the Past Have a Beginning?
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In defense of his claim that the universe must have been created, William Lane Craig gives two distinct philosophical arguments against the possibility of an infinite past. The first appeals to various paradoxes allegedly generated by the idea of an actual infinite. The second appeals to a dynamic theory of the nature of time, and tries to show on that basis that an infinite series of events could not have been “formed by successive addition.” The present paper is concerned with the second of these two arguments. I try to show that it cannot stand on its own independently of the first argument, that Craig does not succeed in defending it against standard objections, and that even those who are inclined to accept a dynamic theory of time should not be convinced by what Craig says in its defense.
13. Philo: Volume > 2 > Issue: 1
E. M. Fales Are the Gods Apolitical?
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
The increasingly strident debate in the United States over the role of religion in public policy raises the general questions whether the United States is a liberal democracy and whether it should be; but also the theoretical question---addressed here---whether it is legitimate for citizens in a liberal democracy to offer religious convictions as grounds for policy. The historically most prominent reason given for the exclusion of religious grounds is that the injection of religion into policy is divisive and potentially destructive of certain rights. I argue another reason, which has been overlooked, is that religious traditions and movements are fundamentally political enterprises that, in effect, introduce foreign agents when permitted institutional participation in domestic politics.
14. Philo: Volume > 2 > Issue: 1
Victor Reppert The Argument from Reason
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In this paper I argue that the existence of human reason gives us good reason to suppose that God exists. If the world were as the materialist supposes it is, then we would not be able to reason to the conclusion that this is so. This contention is often challenged by the claim that mental and physical explanations can be given for the same event. But a close examination of the question of explanatory compatibility reveals that the sort of explanation that would have to be given for the event of, say, inferring that atheism is true, is incompatible with the event being explicable as a purely physical product of a purely physical universe.
discussion
15. Philo: Volume > 2 > Issue: 1
Jim Lippard Historical but Indistinguishable Differences
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Victor Reppert’s paper (pp. 33-45) supposes that there are objectively indistinguishable properties between possible worlds that resultin the property of intentionality existing in one world but not in another objectively indistinguishable world, differing only in their histories. It is also a supposition of Reppert’s paper that proposed ensembles of purely natural properties that lead to the emergence of intentionality fail to do so, but instead only have referential power on the basis of imputed or projected intentionality from human beings. This brief essay examines this supposition and consequence and attempts to provoke more detailed examination of the underlying issues.
16. Philo: Volume > 2 > Issue: 1
Stephen T. Davis Is Belief in the Resurrection Rational?: A Response to Michael Martin
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
This essay is a response to Michael Martin’s “Why the Resurrection Is Initially Improbable,” Philo, Vol. 1, No.1. I argue that Martin has not succeeded in achieving his aim of showing that the Resurrection is initially improbable and thus, by Bayes’s Theorem, implausible. I respond to five of Martin’s arguments: (1) the “particular time and place argument”; (2) the claim that there is no plausible Christian theory of why Jesus should have been incarnated and resurrected; (3) the claim that the Resurrection accounts in the New Testament are unreliable; (4) Martin’s assumptions about how one establishes the initial probability of Resurrection; and (5) the use Martin makes of Bayes’s Theorem to discredit belief in the Resurrection.
17. Philo: Volume > 2 > Issue: 1
Michael Martin Reply to Davis
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
book reviews
18. Philo: Volume > 2 > Issue: 1
Keith M. Parsons Defending Objectivity
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
19. Philo: Volume > 2 > Issue: 1
Jeffery Jay Lowder The Rest of the Story
view |  rights & permissions | cited by