Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Browse by:



Displaying: 1-20 of 23 documents


articles
1. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 65 > Issue: 2
John Hawthorne Deeply Contingent a Priori Knowledge
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
2. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 65 > Issue: 2
Jennifer Whiting Eudaimonia, External Results, and Choosing Virtuous Actions for Themselves
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Aristotle’s requirement that virtuous actions be chosen for themselves is typically interpreted, in Kantian terms, as taking virtuous action to have intrinsic rather than consequentialist value. This raises problems about how to reconcile Aristotle’s requirement with (a) the fact that virtuous actions typically aim at ends beyond themselves (usually benefits to others); and (b) Aristotle’s apparent requirement that everything (including virtuous action) be chosen for the sake of eudaimonia. I offer an alternative interpretation, based on Aristotle’s account of loving a friend for herself, according to which choosing a virtuous action for itself involves choosing it on account of those features of it that make it the kind of action it is, where these features include its intended consequences (such as the benefits it seeks to provide to others). I then suggest that Aristotle may take these consequences (including benefits to others) as contributing (and contributing non-instrumentally) to the agent’s own eudaimonia, and that there is no conflict here with Aristotle’s view that eudaimonia is an activity of the soul. For just as my activity of teaching is actualized in my students (provided they learn from me), so too my virtuous activity can be actualized in its beneficiaries. If this is right, then Aristotle’s view is far from the Stoic (and proto-Kantian) view often attributed to him.
3. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 65 > Issue: 2
Catherine Z. Elgin Take It from Me: The Epistemological Status of Testimony
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Testimony consists in imparting information without supplying evidence or argument to back one’s claims. To what extent does testimony convey epistemic warrant? C. J. A. Coady argues, on Davidsonian grounds, that (1) most testimony is true, hence (2) most testimony supplies warrant sufficient for knowledge. I appeal to Grice’s maxims to undermine Coady’s argument and to show that the matter is more complicated and context-sensitive than is standardly recognized. Informative exchanges take place within networks of shared, tacit assumptions that affect the scope and strength of our claims, and the level of warrant required for their responsible assertion. The maxims explain why different levels of warrant are transferred in different contexts.
4. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 65 > Issue: 2
Stewart Cohen Basic Knowledge and the Problem of Easy Knowledge
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
5. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 65 > Issue: 2
Crispin Wright (Anti-)Sceptics Simple and Subtle: G. E. Moore and John McDowell
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
6. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 65 > Issue: 2
Ralph Wedgwood Internalism Explained
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
symposium
7. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 65 > Issue: 2
Lynne Rudder Baker The Ontological Status of Persons
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Chisholm held that persons are essentially persons. The Constitution View affords a non-Chisholmian way to defend the thesis that persons are essentially persons. The Constitution View shows how persons are constituted by---but not identical to---human animals. On the Constitution View, being a person determines a person’s persistence conditions. On the Animalist View, being an animal determines a person’s persistence conditions.Things of kind K have ontological significance if their persistence conditions are determined by their being members of K. On Chisholm’s view, persons have ontological significance, but animals do not. On Animalism, animals have ontological significance, but persons do not. After explaining the notion of ontological significance, this article argues that persons do have ontological significance, and hence that Animalism is not true.
8. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 65 > Issue: 2
Gary S. Rosenkrantz Reflections on the Ontological Status of Persons
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
9. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 65 > Issue: 2
Lynne Rudder Baker Brief Reply to Rosenkrantz’s Comments on my “The Ontological Status of Persons”
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
book symposium:
10. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 65 > Issue: 2
Scott Soames Précis of Understanding Truth
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
11. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 65 > Issue: 2
Anil Gupta Partially Defined Predicates and Semantic Pathology
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
12. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 65 > Issue: 2
Matthew McGrath Scott Soames: Understanding Truth
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
13. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 65 > Issue: 2
Jamie Tappenden Comments on Soames’ Understanding Truth
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
14. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 65 > Issue: 2
Timothy Williamson Soames on Vagueness
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
15. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 65 > Issue: 2
Scott Soames Replies
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
review essays
16. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 65 > Issue: 2
David Papineau, Nicholas Shea Ruth Millikan’s On Clear and Confused Ideas
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
17. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 65 > Issue: 2
Harold Hodes Stewart Shapiro’s Philosophy of Mathematics
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
critical notices
18. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 65 > Issue: 2
Merold Westphal Hegel’s Idea of a Phenomenology of Spirit
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
19. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 65 > Issue: 2
William Blattner Heidegger’s Philosophy of Being: A Critical Interpretation
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
20. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 65 > Issue: 2
Michael J. White Cause and Explanation in Ancient Greek Thought
view |  rights & permissions | cited by