Cover of Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science
Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Browse by:



Displaying: 1-9 of 9 documents


articles
1. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 36 > Issue: 3
Juan Redmond A free dialogical logic for surrogate reasoning: generation of hypothesis without ontological commitments
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
This article aims to present a Free Dialogic Logic [FDL] as a general framework for hypothesis generation in the practice of modelling in science. Our proposal is based on the idea that the inferential function that models fulfil during the modelling process (surrogate reasoning) should be carried out without ontological commitments. The starting point to achieve our objective is that the scientific consideration of models without a target is a symptom that, on the one hand, the Applicability of Logic should be considered among the conditions of adequacy that should take into account all modeling process and, on the other, that the inferential apparatus at the base of the surrogate reasoning process must be rid of realistic assumptions that lead to erroneous conclusions. In this sense, we propose as an alternative an ontologically neutral inferential system in the perspective of dialogical pragmatism.
2. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 36 > Issue: 3
José Ramón Torices Understanding dogwhistles politics
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
This paper aims to deepen our understanding of so-called covert dogwhistles. I discuss whether a covert dogwhistle is a specific sort of mechanism of manipulation or whether, on the contrary, it draws on other already familiar linguistic mechanisms such as implicatures or presuppositions. I put forward a series of arguments aimed at illustrating that implicatures and presuppositions, on the one hand, and covert dogwhistles, on the other, differ in their linguistic behaviour concerning plausible deniability, cancellability, calculability and mutual acceptance. I concluded this paper by outlining a simple theory for covert dogwhistles according to which they are attitude-foregrounders.
3. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 36 > Issue: 3
Sergio Cermeño-Aínsa Predictive coding and the strong thesis of cognitive penetrability
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In this paper, I discuss the strong thesis of cognitive penetrability (CPs), to wit, th at the perceptual states (P) of a subject (S) are pervasively influenced, affected, or caused by cognitive factors (C) as expectations, memories, thoughts, goals, and so on, at all levels of perceptual processing. I argue that following the predictive coding models of perception (PC), the strong thesis of cognitive penetrability is to be expected.
4. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 36 > Issue: 3
Uku Tooming Politics of Folk Psychology: Believing what Others Believe
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In this paper, I argue that by attributing beliefs the attributer is pushed toward taking a stand on the content of those beliefs and that what stand they take partially depends on the relationship between the attributer and the attributee. In particular, if the attributee enjoys a higher social standing than the attributer, the latter is disposed to adopt the attributed belief, as long as certain other conditions are met. I will call this view the Adoption-by-Attribution model. Because of the non-epistemic influence that derives from the relation of inequality, belief attribution can reinforce the existing unequal power relations and contribute to epistemic injustice.
5. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 36 > Issue: 3
Bruno Borge, Nicolás Lo Guercio Learning from Scientific Disagreement
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
The article addresses the question of how should scientific peers revise their beliefs (if at all) upon recognized disagreement. After presenting the basics of peer disagreement in sections 1 and 2, we focus, in section 3, on a concrete case of scientific disagreement, to wit, the dispute over the evidential status of randomized control trials in medical practice. The examination of this case motivates the idea that some scientific disagreements permit a steadfast reaction. In section 4, we support this conclusion by providing a normative argument in the same direction; if we are correct, typical reasons for conciliation are absent in this kind of scientific disagreements.
6. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 36 > Issue: 3
Javier Anta The epistemic schism of statistical mechanics
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In this paper I will argue that the two main approaches to statistical mechanics, that of Boltzmann and Gibbs, constitute two substantially different theoretical apparatuses. Particularly, I defend that this theoretical split must be philosophically understood as a separation of epistemic functions within this physical domain: while Boltzmannians are able to generate powerful explanations of thermal phenomena from molecular dynamics, Gibbsians can statistically predict observable values in a highly effective way. Therefore, statistical mechanics is a counterexample to Hempel’s (1958) symmetry thesis, where the predictive capacity of a theory is directly correlated with its explanatory potential and vice versa.
7. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 36 > Issue: 3
Miguel Escribano Cabeza La idea de epigénesis en la obra de W. Harvey. Una lectura organicista
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
This paper takes an organicist perspective of W. Harvey’s conception of epigenesis in his work Exercitationes de generatione animalium (1651). In line with this reading, I provide a critical assessment of the different interpretations (mechanistic or vitalist) of Harvey’s idea of epigenesis. The English physician develops his conception of embryogenesis as a process that cannot be understood from the categories of human art, as is apparent in his criticisms towards his teacher, Fabricius. Nor is it accurate to say that his position is animistic. An immersion in this last question will show us his organic conception of the soul, as an extension of the Aristotelian-Galenic tradition.
8. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 36 > Issue: 3
Summary
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
9. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 36 > Issue: 3
Contents of Volume 36
view |  rights & permissions | cited by