Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Browse by:



Displaying: 1-13 of 13 documents


articulos
1. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 18 > Issue: 2
Mario Gómez-Torrente Logical Consequence and Logical Expressions
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
The pretheoretical notions of logical consequence and of a logical expression are linked in vague and complex ways to modal and pragmatic intuitions. I offer an introduction to the difficulties that these intuitions create when one attempts to give precise characterizations of those notions. Special attention is given to Tarski’s theories of logical consequence and logical constancy. I note that the Tarskian theory of logical consequence has fared better in the face of the difficulties than the Tarskian theory of logical constancy. Other theories of these notions are explained and criticized.
2. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 18 > Issue: 2
John P. Burgess Which Modal Models are the Right Ones (for Logical Necessity)?
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Recently it has become almost the received wisdom in certain quarters that Kripke models are appropriate only for something like metaphysical modalities, and not for logical modalities. Here the line of thought leading to Kripke models, and reasons why they are no less appropriate for logical than for other modalities, are explained. It is also indicated where the fallacy in the argument leading to the contrary conclusion lies. The lessons learned are then applied to the question of the status of the formula.
3. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 18 > Issue: 2
Manuel García-Carpintero Gómez-Torrente on Modality and Tarskian Logical Consequence
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Gómez-Torrente’s papers have made important contributions to vindicate Tarski’s model-theoretic account of the logical properties in the face of Etchemendy’s criticisms. However, at some points his vindication depends on interpreting the Tarskian account as purportedly modally deflationary, i.e., as not intended to capture the intuitive modal element in the logical properties, that logical consequence is (epistemic or alethic) necessary truth-preservation. Here it is argued that the views expressed in Tarski’s seminal work do not support this modally deflationary interpretation, even if Tarski himself was sceptical about modalities.
4. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 18 > Issue: 2
William H. Hanson Logic, the A Priori, and the Empirical
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
The time-honored view that logic is a non-empirical enterprise is still widely accepted, but it is not always recognized that there are (at least) two distinct ways in which this view can be made precise. One way focuses on the knowledge we can have of logical matters, the other on the nature of the logical consequence relation itself. More specifically; the first way embodies the claim that knowledge of whether the logical consequence relation holds in a particular case is knowledge that can be had a priori (if at all). The second way presupposes a distinction between structural and non-structural properties and relations, and it holds that logical consequence is to be defined exdusively in terms of the former. It is shown that the two ways are not coextensive by giving an example of a logic that is non-empirical in the second way but not in the first.
5. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 18 > Issue: 2
Ignacio Jané Remarks on Second-Order Consequence
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Tarski’s definition of logical consequence can take different forms when implemented in second order languages, depending on what counts as a model. In the canonical, or standard, version, a model is just an ordinary structure and the (monadic) second-order variables are meant to range over all subsets of its domain. We discuss the dependence of canonical second-order consequence on set theory and raise doubts on the assumption that canonical consequence is a definite relation.
6. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 18 > Issue: 2
Gila Sher A Characterization of Logical Constants Is Possible
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
The paper argues that a philosophically informative and mathematically precise characterization is possible by (i) describing a particular proposal for such a characterization, (ii) showing that certain criticisms of this proposal are incorrect, and (iii) discussing the general issue of what a characterization of logical constants aims at achieving.
7. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 18 > Issue: 2
Mario Gómez-Torrente The ‘Must’ and the ‘Heptahedron’: Remarks on Remarks
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
I offer some brief remarks in reply to comments and criticisms of my earlier work on logical consequence and logical constants. I concentrate on criticisms, especially García-Carpintero’s charge that myviews make no room for modal intuitions about logical consequence, and Sher’s attempted rebuttal of my critique of her theory of logical constants. I show that García-Carpintero’s charge is based on misunderstandings, and that Sher’s attempted rebuttal actually reveals new problems for her theory.
8. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 18 > Issue: 2
Julia Barragán The Perverse Normative Power of Self-Exceptions
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
One of the most disturbing problems of social decision making and indeed quite difficult to resolve is the need to reconcile individual rationality with that of society. While individual rationalizing rules indicateways to maximize benefits without any restriction, the collective point of view tilts toward the limitation of individual maximization. This is the very core of the so-called Prisoner’s Dilemma which is but a formalway of saying that there is good reason for every individual to defect on a bargain; the ‘good reason’, that generally takes the gentler form of a self-exception, is that if a player defects and his opponent does not, then the former profits. The purpose of this study is to show the highly erosive character of this self-exceptions and also to make evident its perverse normative power.
in memoriam
9. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 18 > Issue: 2
Josep E. Corbí Josep Lluís Blasco y la libertad de pensar (1940-2003)
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
recensiones
10. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 18 > Issue: 2
Luis Fernandez Moreno Tractatus logico-philosophicus
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
libros recibidos
11. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 18 > Issue: 2
LIBROS RECIBIDOS / BOOKS RECElVED
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
agenda
12. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 18 > Issue: 2
AGENDA / NOTEBOOK
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
sumario
13. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 18 > Issue: 2
SUMARIO ANALITICO / SUMMARY
view |  rights & permissions | cited by