Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Browse by:



Displaying: 1-10 of 10 documents


news and notes
1. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 29 > Issue: 2
NEWS AND NOTES
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
features
2. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 29 > Issue: 2
Dana Anderson Ethical Sight
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Unconsidered visual acts carry with them embedded presuppositions that arise with the speed of thought. The mind’s virtually instantaneous labeling of objects perceived forces subconscious (though learned) categorization that infects the results obtained from acts seeing acts. Chief among these biased results is a presumed divide between self and other that is both ecologically false and philosophicallydangerous.
3. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 29 > Issue: 2
Simon Hailwood Nature, Landscape, and Neo-Pragmatism
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
A popular if controversial claim, and troublesome for environmental philosophy, ethics, and related disciplines, is that “there is no such thing as nature.” The social constructionist version of this claim makes it difficult to draw a distinction between human and nonhuman nature. In response, first, the concept of landscape can be helpful in drawing this distinction. Second, taking this approach is consistent with at least one interpretation of Richard Rorty’s neopragmatism. Constructionism can be divided into two forms: moderate and radical. Moderate constructionism allows the landscape/nature distinction; radical constructionism excludes it. Rorty’s claim that independent reality is “the world well lost” apparently marks him as a radical constructionist. Nevertheless, the core doctrines of his neopragmatism constitute a moderate constructionism, allowing the nature/landscape distinction. The real problem is Rorty’s anthropocentric instrumentalist characterization of pragmatic justification. Left in place, it rendersneopragmatism a form of radical social constructionism. Redescribing the terms of justification in less anthropocentric instrumentalist terms is consistent with the anti-Platonist core of neopragmatism. Thus redescribed, neopragmatism is fully consistent with the landscape/nature distinction. Anthropocentric instrumentalism, not social constructionism per se, is the problem.
discussion papers
4. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 29 > Issue: 2
Glenn Parson The Aesthetic Value of Animals
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Although recent work in philosophical aesthetics has brought welcome attention to the beauty of nature, the aesthetic appreciation of animals remains rarely discussed. The existence of this gap in aesthetic theory can be traced to certain ethical difficulties with aesthetically appreciating animals. These difficulties can be avoided by focusing on the aesthetic quality of “looking fit for function.” This approach to animal beauty can be defended against the view that “looking fit” is a non-aesthetic quality and against Edmund Burke’s famous critique of the connection between fitness and the beauty of animals.
5. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 29 > Issue: 2
Patrick Frierson Metastandards in the Ethics of Adam Smith and Aldo Leopold
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Adam Smith is not an environmentalist, but he articulated an ethical theory that is increasingly recognized as a fruitful source of environmental ethics. In the context of this theory, Smith illustrates in a particularly valuable way the role that anthropocentric, utilitarian metastandards can play in defending nonanthropocentric, nonutilitarian ethical standpoints. There are four roles that an anthropocentricmetastandard can play in defending an ecocentric ethical standpoint such as Aldo Leopold’s land ethic. First, this metastandard helps reconcile ecocentrism with theodicy, either of the religious sort—showing that God is good—or of the evolutionary sort—showing that ecocentrism is consistent with human ethical dispositions as evolved through a process of natural selection. Second, using anthropocentrism as a metastandard helps reconcile our moral interest in human welfare with a thoroughly ecocentric standpoint. Third, defending ecocentrism by appeal to an anthropocentric metastandard provides a way of swaying die-hard anthropocentrists to adopt a more ecocentric perspective without showing disrespect to nature in the process. Finally, the systematic quasi-ecological connection between ecocentrism as an ethical standard and anthropocentrism as a metastandard has a beauty of its own that can provide additional motive to adhere to ecocentric ethical norms.
6. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 29 > Issue: 2
Lloyd Steffen What Religion Contributes to Environmental Ethics
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Religion and ethics overlap and are in many respects related; yet, they differ in their primary focus of concern. Ethics projects are anthropocentric in that they are constructed in the context of self-other relationships, which includes human beings in relation to the “other” of the natural world, and even religious ethics reflect this relational structure. Religion, however, is focused on the human relation to ultimacy and presents a distinctive consciousness of the self and its relations, including relation to the natural world. As religion decenters the self and reframes how the self is related to the other of the natural world—Thomas Merton and Thich Nhat Hanh articulate this distinctively religious consciousness in relation to the environment—religious consciousness can provide positive support for actions of care and regard toward the natural world. But religion need not go this direction. Focused as it is on ultimacy, which is a power concept that can be dangerous, religion can also sponsor destructive environmental action. Although religion can, indeed, yield in distinctive ways actions and attitudes that amount to support for an ethic of positive regard for the natural world, religiously inspired actions must always be subject to moral critique.
book reviews
7. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 29 > Issue: 2
Susan Armstrong The Ethics of Creativity: Beauty, Morality, and a Processive Cosmos
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
8. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 29 > Issue: 2
Eric Katz Nature by Design: People, Natural Process, and Ecological Restoration
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
9. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 29 > Issue: 2
Robert Kirkman Mindful Conservatism: Rethinking the Ideological and Educational Basis of an Ecologically Sustainable Future
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
10. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 29 > Issue: 2
Ronnie Hawkins Animal Ethics
view |  rights & permissions | cited by