Cover of Process Studies
>> Go to Current Issue

Process Studies

Volume 39, Issue 1, Spring/Summer 2010

Table of Contents

Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Browse by:



Displaying: 1-20 of 22 documents


1. Process Studies: Volume > 39 > Issue: 1
Dan Dombrowski Editor’s Notes
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
articles
2. Process Studies: Volume > 39 > Issue: 1
Arran Gare Toward an Ecological Civilization: The Science, Ethics, and Politics of Eco-Poiesis
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Chinese environmentalists have called for an ecological civilization. To promote this, ecology is defended as the core science embodying process metaphysics,and it is argued that as such ecology can serve as the foundation of such a civilization. Integrating hierarchy theory and Peircian semiotics into this science,it is shown how “community” and “communities of communities,” in which communities are defined by their organization to promote the common good of theircomponents, have to be recognized as central concepts not only of ecology, but of life itself. This perspective is used to defend Lovelock’s “Gaia” hypothesis and the call of Prugh, Costanza, and Daly for strong democracy. An ethics and political philosophy is sketched based on “eco-poiesis” or “home-making,” which is equated with augmenting the life of communities, both human and non-human.
3. Process Studies: Volume > 39 > Issue: 1
Marjorie Hewitt Suchocki The Dynamic God
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Widespread acceptance of Hartshorne’s “correction” of Whitehead’s notion of God inhibited continuing exploration of Whitehead’s own vision of God as a single entity in which the physical and mental poles are reversed. As a result, the implications of this reversed concrescence have been paid scant attention. Whitehead himself did little more than hint at the consequences. My thesis is that consideration of a reversed concrescence highlights the essential dynamism of God as a whole, including the primordial nature, and has implications for the provision of initial aims for the world.
4. Process Studies: Volume > 39 > Issue: 1
Robert J. Valenza Metaphysical Models
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Materialism, epiphenomenalism, dualism, idealism, and dual-aspect theories may all be represented by an appealing abstract mathematical devicecalled a commutative diagram. Properties of the components of such diagrams characterize and, to some extent, even parameterize these systems and attendant metaphysical concepts (such as causal closure and supervenience) in a unified framework; process thought is of particular interest in this connection. In many cases we can even exemplify the theories typified by these diagrams in explicit graphical models. All of this tends to clarify the relationships among key philosophical positions and to sharpen our sense of the effective domain and principal limitations of each. Systematic variation of these abstract diagrams may even suggest cogent metaphysical systems yet to be examined.
5. Process Studies: Volume > 39 > Issue: 1
Edgar A. Towne All Causality Occurs in a Present: G.H. Mead’s Proposal to Process Philosophy
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
G.H. Mead and A.N. Whitehead agree that all causation occurs in a present, that the self is social, and that philosophical description of the new physics of relativity and quantum mechanics is a complicated task. I explore this complexity in relation to the knowledge of events unable to be observed here and now, especially past historical events. The integration of the two philosophers’ views is shown in reference to Whitehead’s criteria of respect for facts and coherence. By reference to the work of Palmyre Oomen I show the inconsistency of Whitehead’s treatment of the prehensibility of God’s consequent nature with his claim thatGod is not an exception to the metaphysical principles. The integration of Mead’s and Whitehead’s views permits plausible talk about past, present, and futureconsisent with our scientific knowledge.
6. Process Studies: Volume > 39 > Issue: 1
Joseph A. Bracken, S.J. God, Chance and Purpose: Implications for Process Theology
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In God, Chance and Purpose, David Bartholomew uses probability theory to show how Divine Providence can be active in a world governed by chance and necessity. At the micro-level of Nature God uses a statistical formula to control the outcome of seemingly random events; at the macro-level God influences but does not control the outcome of events. From a Whiteheadian perspective “the common element of form” of a society could be seen as the equivalent of Bartholomew’s statistical formula but generated in each case from the bottom-up rather than imposed from the top-down. Yet Bartholomew’s insistence that statistical formulas only work with large groups of entities suggests that more attention should be given by Whiteheadians to the workings of Divine Providence onsocieties as opposed to individual actual entities.
7. Process Studies: Volume > 39 > Issue: 1
Yoshihiro Hayashi Introducing a Time Horizon into Ethics
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Modern technology has radically altered the conditions for human action, endowing us with tremendous power to affect the future. Patterns of action that appear positive in their short-term effects must sometimes be judged unsustainable. Hans Jonas and Thomas Berry are among those who emphasize the necessity of transforming ethics in light of these considerations. In a Whiteheadian framework, this needed transformation is rooted in the nature of things.
special focus section: eternal objects and future contingents
8. Process Studies: Volume > 39 > Issue: 1
George W. Shields, Derek Malone-France Introduction to Special Focus Issue on Eternal Objects and Future Contingents
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
9. Process Studies: Volume > 39 > Issue: 1
Derek Malone-France Between Hartshorne and Molina: A Whiteheadian Conception of Divine Foreknowledge
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
The doctrine of inerrant divine “middle knowledge” of future contingent events, first developed by the sixteenth century Jesuit theologian Luis de Molina, has resurfaced as a prominent position within contemporary debates over divine foreknowledge, creaturely freedom, and the ontological status of possibilities. As yet, the only substantive response to the new Molinism from a process perspective has come in a brief section on “Hartshorne and the Challenge of Molinism,” in an essay on Hartshorne’s view of “The Logic of Future Contingents” by George W. Shields and Donald W. Viney, in Shields’ edited anthology Process and Analysis.Shields and Viney offer an insightful critique of Molinism. However, their use of Hartshorne’s understanding of possibility presents problems for those, like me, who prefer Whitehead’s more robustly realist notion of eternal objects. Here, I defend Whitehead’s Platonism from the main lines of criticism leveled against itby Hartshorne, while demonstrating that a “thick” conception of the objective content of the possible within the context of the divine understanding need not crossover into a deterministic conception of God’s foreknowledge, à la Molina.
10. Process Studies: Volume > 39 > Issue: 1
George W. Shields Eternal Objects, Middle Knowledge, and Hartshorne: A Response to Derek Malone-France
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In this essay I argue that Malone-France’s anti-realistic interpretation of the Hartshorne-Peirce theory of possibles can be challenged in a number of ways. While his interpretation does suggest that there are in fact two distinct accounts of possibility in Hartshorne’s philosophy, one that is vulnerable to an antirealistic interpretation and one that is not, Hartshorne does have a consistent and defensible doctrine of possibles. I argue that Whitehead’s contrasting “nonprotean”theory of possibles or “eternal objects” has its own set of conundrums to face, including problems with the coherence of the notion of the completeness of eternal objects and problems with infinite regresses. Whether Whitehead’s or Hartshorne’s account of possibles is correct, I concur with Malone-France that the Molinist doctrine of divine knowledge of future contingents is flawed.
11. Process Studies: Volume > 39 > Issue: 1
Derek Malone-France Reply to Shields
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
12. Process Studies: Volume > 39 > Issue: 1
Donald Wayne Viney Objects, Eternal and Otherwise, and the Process Response to Molinism: Response to Malone-France and Shields
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
reviews
13. Process Studies: Volume > 39 > Issue: 1
John W. Lango Leibniz, Whitehead and the Metaphysics of Causation
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
14. Process Studies: Volume > 39 > Issue: 1
Qing Huang A Worldview for the Ecological Age: A Comparative Study of Ecological Theologies of J. Moltmann and J. Cobb, Jr.
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
15. Process Studies: Volume > 39 > Issue: 1
Daniel Dombrowski Deep Postmodernism: Whitehead, Wittgenstein, Merleau-Ponty, and Polanyi
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
16. Process Studies: Volume > 39 > Issue: 1
Phil Jenkins Deep Empiricism: Kant, Whitehead, and the Necessity of Philosophical Theism
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
17. Process Studies: Volume > 39 > Issue: 1
Pauline Phemister Process-relational Philosophy: An Introduction To Alfred North Whitehead
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
18. Process Studies: Volume > 39 > Issue: 1
Jerry D. Korsmeyer Metaphysics and the Future of Theology: The Voice of Theology in Public Life
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
19. Process Studies: Volume > 39 > Issue: 1
Roland Faber Handbook of Whiteheadian Process Thought
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
20. Process Studies: Volume > 39 > Issue: 1
Hui Dong Process Studies in China
view |  rights & permissions | cited by