Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Browse by:



Displaying: 1-12 of 12 documents


articles
1. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 5 > Issue: 2
Marilyn McCord Adams Problems of Evil: More Advice to Christian Philosophers
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
The argument that(1) God exists, and is omniscient, omnipotent, and perfectly goodand(2) Evil existsare logically incompatible, can be construed aporetically (as generating a puzzle and posing the constructive challenge of finding a solution that displays their compatibility) or atheologically (as a positive proof of the non-existence of God). I note that analytic philosophers of religion over the last thirty years or so have focused on the atheological deployment of the argument from evil, and have met its onslaughts from the posture of defense. I take Nelson Pike (in his article “Hume on Evil”) and Alvin Plantinga (in The Nature of Necessity, “Self-Profile,” and other pieces) as paradigm defenders, analyse their approaches, and try to make explicit parameters and assumptions within which these defenses have been conducted. In particular, both writers seem to attempt a reply within the parameters of a religion-neutral value theory and on the assumption that God has obligations to do one thing rather than another in creation-both of which conspire to defend God as a producer of global goods and shift attention off the more pressing question of His agent-centered goodness. I then argue that value-theory pluralism explodes the myth of shared values, and so complicates the structure of fair-minded debate about the problem of evil as to significantly limit the utility of defense. I invite Christian philosophers to approach the problem aporetically, and to exhibit the compossibility of (1) and (2) by formulating their own beliefs about how God is solving the problem of evil using the valuables within a Christian value theory to defeat evils. After sketching a strategy for doing this, I answer the objection that my recommendation conflates Christian philosophy and theology, and try to show how it affords a continuity between the so-called philosophical and existential problems of evil.
2. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 5 > Issue: 2
James A. Keller Reflections on a Methodology for Christian Philosophers
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In a recent article in FAITH AND PHILOSOPHY, Alvin Plantinga advised Christian philosophers to philosophize in light of their fundamental beliefs as Christians. Believing that his discussion does not give proper weight to the necessary role of secular beliefs in modifying our Christian beliefs, in this article I propose that Christian beliefs and secular beliefs should be related more dialectically than Plantinga suggests--i.e., that neither should always be given precedence. I defend this proposal with several examples on a variety of topics from the history of Christian thought and suggest how much weight to give to beliefs of each type.
3. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 5 > Issue: 2
Alvin Plantinga Method in Christian Philosophy: A Reply
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
4. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 5 > Issue: 2
James A. Keller Method in Christian Philosophy: Further Reflections
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
5. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 5 > Issue: 2
John H. Whittaker Kierkegaard and Existence Communications
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Kierkegaard occasionally mentions a type of belief which he calls an “existence communication,” and his discussion of such beliefs parallels his discussion of subjective truths (in the Concluding Unscientific Postscript). Existence communications include religious beliefs. I suggest that it is less misleading to focus on this term than it is to wrestle with the difficult and overworked notion of subjective truths; ultimately, his view of religious beliefs can be seen more clearly.His view does not fully emerge, however, without the assistance of some other concepts. My thesis is that existence communications are comparable in their resistance to objective forms of adjudication to first principles, and comparable in their “self-involving” characteristics to teleological principles about the “raison d’etre of existence.This account not only helps to clarify Kierkegaard’s discussion, but it also offers two important hints about modern problems regarding religious belief. It suggest that religious claims may indeed be truth claims, and it suggests that there is more to the justification than comes out in a consideration of evidence.
6. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 5 > Issue: 2
Richard L. Purtill Fatalism and the Omnitemporality of Truth
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In this paper I will show that the omnitemporality of truth does indeed imply fatalism if the past is unchangeable. I then argue that it is very likely indeed that the past is unchangeable and thus, since it is very likely that fatalism is false, it is very likely that the doctrine of the omnitemporality of truth is false. I argue that the rejection of the omnitemporality of truth has no undesirable consequences for either logic or theology, that in fact the logical and theological consequences of the rejection of the omnitemporality of truth are beneficial to both disciplines.
7. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 5 > Issue: 2
Georges Dicker A Refutation of Rowe’s Critique of Anselm’s Ontological Argument
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In William L. Rowe’s “The Ontological Argument,” an essay that appears in the most recent editions of Feinberg’s Reason and Responsibility and as a chapter in Rowe’s Philosophy of Religion, Rowe reconstructs Anselm’s Proslogium II argument for the existence of God, surveys critically several standard objections to it, and presents an original critique. Although Rowe’s reconstruction is perspicuous and his criticisms of the standard objections are judicious, his own critique, I argue, leaves Anselm’s argument unscathed. I conclude with some programmatic remarks about what a more adequate critique of Anselm’s argument should do.
8. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 5 > Issue: 2
William L. Rowe Response to Dicker
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
9. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 5 > Issue: 2
Georges Dicker A Note on Rowe’s “Response to Dicker”
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
book reviews
10. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 5 > Issue: 2
Huston Smith Christianity/Islam: Essays on Esoteric Ecumenism
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
11. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 5 > Issue: 2
William J. Wainwright Religious Experience
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
12. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 5 > Issue: 2
Edward Wierenga Alvin Plantinga
view |  rights & permissions | cited by