Cover of The Review of Metaphysics
Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Browse by:



Displaying: 1-20 of 26 documents


articles
1. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 71 > Issue: 2
Franklin I. Gamwell A Defense of Metaphysical Necessity
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Against the widely affirmed dictum, “all existential statements (that is, statements of the form “something that is x exists”) can be denied without self-contradiction,” this essay argues for some existential statements being necessarily true semantically and thus for transcendental metaphysics in the strict sense. Having briefly reviewed how Ronald Dworkin, Karl-Otto Apel, and Thomas Nagel each affirm the dictum in question and, thereby, imply the possible truth of the statement, “nothing exists,” the essay seeks to show how the statement, “‘nothing exists’ is possibly true” (not simply “nothing exists”), is pragmatically self-refuting. Against the implications of subjectivity as such, that statement implies the impossibility of knowing any existential statement; that is, knowing what exists or, indeed, whether anything exists is forever denied to us. The dictum is, therefore, itself impossible, and the essay concludes with the assertion that transcendental metaphysics should be neoclassical.
2. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 71 > Issue: 2
Howard J. Curzer Akrasia and Courage in the Protagoras
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Akratic agents know what is best, can do it, do not do it, and rationalize. According to Socrates, seemingly akratic agents are confused, ignorant of what is best. According to the Many, they are overcome, unable to do what is best. Unlike Socrates and the Many, Plato rejects hedonism and psychological egoism, but not the existence of akratic acts in the Socratic reductio (351b–358c). Counterexamples to both Socrates’ mismeasure account and the Many’s overpowering account pervade Greek literature and even the Protagoras itself. In the courage-is-wisdom arguments (349d–351a, 358c–360e), Plato again argues against hedonism and psychological egoism, and advances an Aristotelian definition of courage.
3. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 71 > Issue: 2
Benjamin S. Yost Kant’s Theory of Motivation: A Hybrid Approach
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
To vindicate morality against skeptical doubts, Kant must show that agents can be moved to act independently of their sensible desires. Kant must therefore answer a motivational question: how does an agent get from the cognition that she ought to act morally to acting morally? Affectivist interpretations of Kant hold that agents are moved to act by feelings, while intellectualists appeal to cognition alone. To overcome the significant shortcomings of each view, the author develops a hybrid theory of motivation. His central interpretive claim is that Kant is a special kind of motivational internalist: on Kant’s view, agents are moved to act by a feeling of intellectual pleasure at the prospect of accomplishing a task they have set for themselves, a feeling that originates in free choice. The resulting theory is immune to the challenges facing intellectualism and affectivism, thus strengthening the prospects of Kant’s justification of morality.
4. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 71 > Issue: 2
Leemon B. McHenry Whitehead and Russell on the Analysis of Matter
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
While Whitehead and Russell’s collaboration on the foundations of mathematics ended with the publication of Principia Mathematica, both philosophers separately developed a philosophy of physics in the 1920s that was based on the revolutionary advances in modern physics. This essay explores the affinities and contrasts in Whitehead and Russell’s event ontology as a metaphysical foundation of physics and demonstrates the influence of Whitehead’s method of extensive abstraction on Russell’s metaphysics and epistemology.
5. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 71 > Issue: 2
Louis Dupré Heidegger’s Interpretation of Poetry and the Transcendent Openness of Being
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Heidegger’s commentaries on Hölderlin’s poetry constitute an essential part of his philosophical heritage. They played a decisive role in the move from a self-enclosed theory of Being to a transcendent openness. Nietzsche confirmed Heidegger’s aversion of the philosophical subjectivism that had come to paralyze all of Western philosophy and, related with it, threatened Western culture with collapse. The time before and during World War I confirmed both the consequences of a philosophical subjectivism and the urgent need for an active political attitude. Heidegger’s support of Nietzsche did not outlast the war nor the information that the will to power’s political interpretation was not Nietzsche’s own but his sister’s and had become a secret weapon in the service of the Nazi party. By that time Heidegger studied Hölderlin’s poetry and understood that also his own philosophy of Being had been rigid and one-sided. From Hölderlin’s poetry he learned the indispensability of passive attitudes. Thus far atheism had served as protection of the absoluteness of a self-enclosed Being. Through the poems of Hölderlin Heidegger learned that Being is not a self-supporting absolute but a transcendent openness that might be expressed actively in religion or in a mystical Gelassenheit.
book reviews
6. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 71 > Issue: 2
Alex Priou Sophistry and Political Philosophy: Protagoras’ Challenge to Socrates
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
7. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 71 > Issue: 2
Allison Krile Thornton Animalism: New Essays on Persons, Animals, and Identity
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
8. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 71 > Issue: 2
Michael P. Krom Politics for a Pilgrim Church: A Thomistic Theory of Civic Virtue
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
9. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 71 > Issue: 2
David Rohr Deep Pantheism: Toward a New Transcendentalism
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
10. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 71 > Issue: 2
Joseph M. Forte The City-State of the Soul: Constituting the Self in Plato’s Republic
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
11. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 71 > Issue: 2
Daniel Shields Ethics as a Work of Charity: Thomas Aquinas on Pagan Virtue
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
12. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 71 > Issue: 2
Tom Sparrow Embodiment, Enaction, and Culture: Investigating the Constitution of the Shared World
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
13. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 71 > Issue: 2
Andrew Israelsen The Intolerable God: Kant’s Theological Journey
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
14. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 71 > Issue: 2
Duane H. Davis Perception and Its Development in Merleau-Ponty’s Phenomenology
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
15. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 71 > Issue: 2
Michael Zuckert Naïve Readings: Reveilles Political and Philosophic
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
16. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 71 > Issue: 2
Peeter Müürsepp Understanding Scientific Progress: Aim-Oriented Empiricism
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
17. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 71 > Issue: 2
Jude P. Dougherty Philosophical Provocations: 55 Short Essays
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
18. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 71 > Issue: 2
Curtis L. Hancock The A Priori in the Thought of Descartes: Cognition, Method and Science
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
19. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 71 > Issue: 2
Jean Rioux The Figure of Nature: On Greek Origins
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
20. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 71 > Issue: 2
Robert Miner Nietzsche’s Earth: Great Events, Great Politics
view |  rights & permissions | cited by