Cover of Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy
Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Browse by:



Displaying: 1-18 of 18 documents


1. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 14 > Issue: 27
Maria Luísa Ribeiro Ferreira Abertura
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
artigos
2. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 14 > Issue: 27
Adela Cortina Ciudadanía Intercultural
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Ce texte expose le concept de citoyenneté dans son double aspect - descriptif et prescriptif. Aux dimensions civiles, politiques et sociales de la citoyenneté il faut ajouter deux autres: l’économique et la culturelle. Ce qui fait tenir en compte le problème du multiculturalisme et de la citoyenneté multiculturelle. Il faut trouver des réponses qui permettent aux différentes éthnies une façon de vivre ensemble. Dans ce but, l’article analyse critiquement trois possibilités: le libéralisme multiculturel de Klymcka; le libéralis me intolérant de Sartori et le libéralisme radical interculturel. Ce dernier est la position choisie et soutenue dans le texte qui vise souligner le caractère dynamique des différentes cultures, bien que l’influence bénéfique qu’elles provoquent les unes sur les autres.
3. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 14 > Issue: 27
Raúl Fornet-Bettancourt Interculturalidad o Barbarie. 11 Tests Provisionales Para el Mejoramiento de las Teorías y Prácticas de la Interculturalidad como Alternativa de Otra Humanidad
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Pour éviter que le destin de l’humanité soit «la prison ou l’hospice d’aliénés» il faut faire attention aux mutations théoriques et pratiques qui puissent développer l’interculturalité. Celle-ci est es sentielle pour la survie du planète. La thèse soutenue dans cet article est que l’alternative à la multiculturalité est la barbarie. Il faut modifier le travail d’investigation et les pratiques habituelles développées sur ce thème. On doit proposer d’autres orientations philosophiques et d’autres pratiques, qui ne s’inscrivent pas sur des vérités absolues et sur des lois universelles, des orientations qui rejettent les implications d’uniformité de la globalization néo-libérale. Le recours à la théologie de la libération et à l’antropologie philosophique critique est importante.
4. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 14 > Issue: 27
Carlos João Correia Questões de Teodiceia na Cultura Ocidental
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
This paper examines the philosophical conflict arisen by theodicy in western culture. After the exposition of Simon Blackburn and Richard Swinbume’s contentions views, we sustain that the only credible solution to the problem entails a new philosophical concept of God based on a non-anthropocentric vision of reality.
5. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 14 > Issue: 27
Markus Gabriel Metafísica e Mitologia
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Since it can reasonably be taken for granted that the Gods of pagan mythology have been products of human cognitive activities, there is an obvious relation between our most general concepts of consciousness and the possibility of an understanding of mythology. In order to hint at the insuffiency of the modern idea of an autonomous subject, which is devoid of any content that cannot be construed as a moment of self-conscious reflection, it is necessary to go back to both ancient greek metaphysics and mythology. Ancient metaphysics does not yet fully articulate the idea of an autonomous subjectivity (even though the latter would not have been possible without the former). Therefore, it is better understood in terms of ontonomy, i.e. metaphysical thought of what there ultimately is. In the paper it is argued that metaphysical ontonomy has its origin in mythological theonomy. The very idea of an emancipation of logos from myth is itself mythological. Hence, self-consciousness may be interpreted as a self-explication of mythology. In the very act of reflecting itself in human consciousness, the “Being” hides its mythological, artistic nature. However, this could not be made intelligible without the help of mythology itself because it is impossible to talk about Ontonomy let alone Theonomy in theoretical propositions.
6. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 14 > Issue: 27
António Manuel Hespanha As Corese a Instituição da Ordem no Mundo do Antigo Regime
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
The colors are one of the most expressive examples of social and personal construction of meanings (if not of the reality itself). The diverse cultures have seen different colors in the rainbow, they have organized differently their sequence in it, but, overall, they have loaded them with different symbolic contents. Frequently, colors are markers of the social and political hierarchies and, therefore, “matter of law”. In the second half of the 18th Century, a disciple of Christian Thomasius summarizes, in a university dissertation, the common legal prescriptions on the use of the colors. Old literal genealogies still stand, entangled with scientific opinions of the time. On the basis of this intertext, legal doctrine fixes and multiplies meanings over space and time, as a huge space of industrial symbolic production. In such a way that, in spite of the changes brought by romantic imagery and by the emergent industrial revolution in the techniques of coloring, we can still recognize some glimpses of the shattered world of colors of traditional Europe.
7. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 14 > Issue: 27
António Joaquim Rocha Martins Filosofia e Literatura. O Paradigma Bonaventuriano
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
This paper analyses (1) the power of metaphor which is central to Bonaventure’s literary expression, his spirituality, his philosophical and theological speculation; (2) Considers which human language is ultimately a participation in divine expressionism; (3) Analyses the notion of metaphor in Bonaventure’s treatment of human language; (4) Expose his contribution for the «linguistic turn». All of this will support the thesis of this paper: that language as expression is the most fundamental metaphysical/ontological/poetic notion in Bonaventure’s vision.
8. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 14 > Issue: 27
José António Leite Cruz de Matos Pacheco O Platonismo de Marcel Proust: Tempo, Memória, Sentido
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Marcel Proust is not known as a philosopher. Nevertheless, his monumental masterpiece, In Search for Lost Time, must be understood as a System - not a «philosophical System», but a System sustained and moved by a philosophy of existence: «System of existence itself»; «System of time» in its mere occurrence. Memory becomes here, in face of time, an almost sacred way of revealing sense: and sense - the sense that one can see and understand by this work of memory - somehow emerges like a perfect, platonical form, that brings happiness and is wisdom, not as if we have already seen it in a previous life of the soul, but in the process of making its own rememberance and comprehension.
9. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 14 > Issue: 27
António Lopes Relativismo na Avaliação de Execuções Musicais
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
As in other domains of art, the assessment of performances or interpretations of musical works is largely considered as a matter of personal taste. In Evaluating Musical Performance, Jerrold Levinson argues that relativism, in this matter, depends on the many interests with which a performance can be faced, and, consequently, evaluated and assessed. My thesis in this article is that not all interests have the same importance and that there is a “purely musical” perspective that must prevail over the other interests. This way I try to diminish the so called relativism.
10. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 14 > Issue: 27
João Paulo de Oliveira Cruz Mendes Indivíduo e Realidade: De Simmel a Kracauer
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
This article is about the influence of Georg Simmel on Siegfried Kracauer’s thought and analysis method, and also on the difference between the two. Kracauer was Simmel’s pupil at Berlin in 1907, and exposed his thought and method in an essay (Georg Simmel) published for the first time in 1963, forty-two years after being written, in a collection of papers intituled Das Ornament der Masse. Starting from a heuristic principle - which could be put like this: all expressions of spiritual/intellectual life are interrelated in countless ways; no single one can be extricated from this web of relations, since each is enmeshed in the web with all other such expressions - , Kracauer distinguished, in Simmel’s method, two different ways of linking the different phenomena: discovering its essential congruence [Wesenszusammengehörigkeit] or by analogy [Analogie]. The first method shows how disparate phenomena could have the same source. The second tries to demonstrate similitudes between phenomena, and it is, in a certain degree, an abstract construction. This double approach of reality synchronizes Kracauer’s worries on the culture fragmentation and his attempt to overcome it. This is most clear when he criticizes Simmel, in a forward step, of being in default of metaphor [Gleichnis]. Metaphor is, in Kracauer’s point of view, not only a relation between objects, like Simmel tries, but a relation between subject and object, and the representation by a particular image of individual things as much as of the entire world. Metaphor carries in it itself the philosophical intuition that is lacking in Simmel’s oeuvre.
11. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 14 > Issue: 27
Emanuel Angelo da Rocha Fragoso O Conceito de Liberdade na Ética de Espinosa
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Dans la plus grande oeuvre de Benedictus de Espinosa, son Éthique, la délimitation de l’univers ontologique, outre le fait de discerner les éléments constitutifs de sa Philosophia en général, résulte entre autre d’un cadre conceptuel pour le principal sujet de son éthique: la liberté. Ayant l’intention d’expliciter les relations entre l’ontologie spinoziste et le concept de liberté, en so ulignant l’importance de ce concept au sein du système de Espinosa en général et sa spécificité à l’intérieur de l'Éthique en particulier, nous expliciterons le concept de liberté dans cette oeuvre: la Définition 7 de la Partie 1. Dans cette définition composée de deux parties distinctes, Espinosa ira opposer “chose libre” (res libera) et “contrainte” (coacta), la première consistant à celle qui “existe exclusivement par nécessité de sa nature et est par soi-même déterminé à agir”, et la seconde à “ce qui est déterminé par autre chose à exister et à opérer de certaine manière déterminée”. Ensuite, nous procéderons à l’analyse critique du concept traditionnel de liberté mise en relation avec la volonté et la contingence, que ce soit comme un pouvoir de choisir ou comme un pouvoir de décision ou d’être régia par un modèle, vis-à-vis des causes qui détermineraient la liberté de la volonté ou absoluto beneplacito, ou encore, de ce qui la régit, en visant la caractérisation de la liberté comme autonomie nécessaire à l’existence et à l’action, ou comme nécessité intrinsèque attachée à l’essence et à ce dont elle découle. En outre, nous analyserons aussi les dédoublements de cette définition initiale suivant leurs relations avec la volonté (finie ou infinie) comme faculté et avec l’accord (fini ou infini), en tant qu’absents de l’e ssence divine, et, finalement, avec la nécessité même.
12. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 14 > Issue: 27
Luís Machado de Abreu A Cultura sob o Ponto de Vista da Filosofia: (Ao Encontro de Manuel Antunes)
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
La dimension culturelle de l’humain ne s’épuise jamais dans les étud es culturelles. Elle demande une réflexion radicale sur le phénomène culturel total dont la tâche appartient à la philosophie de la culture. L’oeuvre de Manuel Antunes (1918-1985) esquisse une approche stimulante et réussie de cette discipline nettement inscrite sous l’horizon de l’ontologie.
debate
13. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 14 > Issue: 27
Roberto R. Aramayo Mendacidad y Rebelión en Kant: (Glosas al Presunto Derecho de Mentir por Filantropía: Un Debate con Aylton Barbieri Durão)
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Based on the ethic formalism, Kant develops a rigorist interpretation of political and juridical philosophy that leads both to the unconditional condemnation of lies, for which there are no possible cases of exception, such as the lie to support philanthropy, or the lie to support needs, and to the total negation of the subjects’ right to resistance, even against the sovereign’s unfair decisions, although the realization of morality in the history of philosophy explains his enthusiasm regarding successful revolutions.
recensões
14. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 14 > Issue: 27
José António Leite Cruz de Matos Pacheco Tratado dos Três Impostores, Moisés, Jesus , Maomé
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
15. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 14 > Issue: 27
José António Leite Cruz de Matos Pacheco Carlos João Correia, Mitos e Narrativas. Ensaios Sobre a Experiência do Mal
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
16. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 14 > Issue: 27
Maria Luísa Ribeiro Ferreira Fernanda Henriques, Filosofia e Literatura. Um Percurso Hermenêutico com Paul Ricoeur
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
tese
17. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 14 > Issue: 27
José Artur Vitória de Sousa Ramos O Auto-Retrato ou a Reversibilidade do Rosto
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
18. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 14 > Issue: 27
Renato Epifânio Repertório de Bibliografia Filosófica Portuguesa (1988-2002)
view |  rights & permissions | cited by