Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Browse by:



Displaying: 1-18 of 18 documents


articles
1. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 70 > Issue: 2
William Alston Perception and Representation
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
I oppose the popular view that the phenomenal character of perceptual experience consists in the subject’s representing the (putative) perceived object as being so-and-so. The account of perceptual experience I favor instead is a version of the “Theory of Appearing” that takes it to be a matter of the perceived object’s appearing to one as so-and-so, where this does not mean that the subject takes or believes it to be so-and-so. This plays no part in my criticisms of Representationalism. I mention it only to be up front as to where I stand. My criticism of the Representationalist position is in sections. (1) There is no sufficient reason for positing a representative function for perceptual experience. It doesn’t seem on the face of it to be that, and nothing serves in place of such seeming. (2) Even if it did have such a function, it doesn’t have the conceptual resources to represent a state of affairs. (3) Even if it did, it is not suited to represent, e.g., a physical property of color. (4) Finally, even if I am wrong about the first three points, it is still impossible for the phenomenal character of the perceptual experience to consist in its representing what it does. My central argument for this central claim of the paper is that it is metaphysically, de re possible that one have a certain perceptual experience without it’s presenting any state of affairs. And since all identities hold necessarily, this identity claim fails.
2. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 70 > Issue: 2
Wayne A. Davis Concepts and Epistemic Individuation
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Christopher Peacocke has presented an original version of the perennial philosophical thesis that we can gain substantive metaphysical and epistemological insight from an analysis of our concepts. Peacocke’s innovation is to look at how concepts are individuated by their possession conditions, which he believes can be specified in terms of conditions in which certain propositions containing those concepts are accepted. The ability to provide such insight is one of Peacocke’s major arguments for his theory of concepts. I will critically examine this “fruitfulness” argument by looking at one philosophical problem Peacocke uses his theory to solve and treats in depth.Peacocke (1999, 2001) defines what he calls the “Integration Challenge.” The challenge is to integrate our metaphysics with our epistemology by showing that they are mutually acceptable. Peacocke’s key conclusion is that the Integration Challenge can be met for “epistemically individuated concepts.” A good theory of content, he believes, will close the apparent gap between an account of truth for any given subject matter and an overall account of knowledge. I shall argue that there are no epistemically individuated concepts, and shall critically analyze Peacocke’s arguments for their existence. I will suggest more generally that the possession conditions of concepts and their principles of individuation shed little light on the epistemology or metaphysics of things other than concepts. My broader goal is to shed light on what concepts are by showing that they are more fundamental than the sorts of cognitive and epistemic factors a leading theory uses to define them.
3. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 70 > Issue: 2
Gene Witmer, William Butchard, Kelly Trogdon Intrinsicality without Naturalness
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Rae Langton and David Lewis have proposed an account of “intrinsic property” that makes use of two notions: being independent of accompaniment and being natural. We find the appeal to the first of these promising; the second notion, however, we find mystifying. In this paper we argue that the appeal to naturalness is not acceptable and offer an alternative definition of intrinsicality. The alternative definition makes crucial use of a notion commonly used by philosophers, namely, the notion of one property being had in virtue of another property. We defend our account against three arguments for thinking that this “in virtue of” notion is unacceptable in this context. We also take a look at a variety of cases in which the definition might be applied and defend it against potential counterexamples. The upshot, we think, is a modest but adequate account of what we understand by “intrinsic property.”
4. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 70 > Issue: 2
Luciano Floridi Is Semantic Information Meaningful Data?
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
There is no consensus yet on the definition of semantic information. This paper contributes to the current debate by criticising and revising the Standard Definition of semantic Information (SDI) as meaningful data, in favour of the Dretske-Grice approach: meaningful and well-formed data constitute semantic information only if they also qualify as contingently truthful. After a brief introduction, SDI is criticised for providing necessary but insufficient conditions for the definition of semantic information. SDI is incorrect because truth-values do not supervene on semantic information, and misinformation (that is, false semantic information) is not a type of semantic information, but pseudo-information, that is not semantic information at all. This is shown by arguing that none of the reasons for interpreting misinformation as a type of semantic information is convincing, whilst there are compelling reasons to treat it as pseudo-information. As a consequence, SDI is revised to include a necessary truth-condition. The last section summarises the main results of the paper and indicates some interesting areas of application of the revised definition.
5. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 70 > Issue: 2
Donald L. M. Baxter Altruism, Grief, and Identity
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
The divide between oneself and others has made altruism seem irrational to some thinkers, as Sidgwick points out. I use characterizations of grief, especially by St. Augustine, to question the divide, and use a composition-as-identity metaphysics of parts and wholes to make literal sense of those characterizations.
6. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 70 > Issue: 2
Brian Kierland, Bradley Monton Minimizing Inaccuracy for Self-Locating Beliefs
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
One’s inaccuracy for a proposition is defined as the squared difference between the truth value (1 or 0) of the proposition and the credence (or subjective probability, or degree of belief) assigned to the proposition. One should have the epistemic goal of minimizing the expected inaccuracies of one’s credences. We show that the method of minimizing expected inaccuracy can be used to solve certain probability problems involving information loss and self-locating beliefs (where a self-locating belief of a temporal part of an individual is a belief about where or when that temporal part is located). We analyze the Sleeping Beauty problem, the duplication version of the Sleeping Beauty problem, and various related problems.
7. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 70 > Issue: 2
John Hawthorne Chance and Counterfactuals
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Suppose the world is chancy. The worry arises that most ordinary counterfactuals are false. This paper examines David Lewis’ strategy for rescuing such counterfactuals, and argues that it is highly problematic.
discussions
8. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 70 > Issue: 2
Peter J. Markie Easy Knowledge
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Stewart Cohen has recently presented solutions to two forms of what he calls “The Problem of Easy Knowledge” (“Basic Knowledge and the Problem of Easy Knowledge,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, LXV, 2, September 2002, pp. 309-329). I offer alternative solutions. Like Cohen’s, my solutions allow for basic knowledge. Unlike his, they do not require that we distinguish between animal and reflective knowledge, restrict the applicability of closure under known entailments, or deny the ability of basic knowledge to combine with self-knowledge to provide inductive evidential support. My solution to the closure version of the problem covers a variation on the problem that is immune to Cohen’s approach. My response to the bootstrapping version presents reasons to question whether the problem case, as Cohen presents it, is even possible, and, assuming it is, my solution avoids a false implication of Cohen’s own. The key to my solutions for both versions is the distinction between an inference’s transferring epistemic support, on the one hand, and its not begging the question against skeptics, on the other.
9. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 70 > Issue: 2
Stewart Cohen Why Basic Knowledge is Easy Knowledge
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
book symposium
10. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 70 > Issue: 2
Timothy Williamson Précis of Knowledge and its Limits
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
11. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 70 > Issue: 2
Anthony Brueckner Knowledge, Evidence, and Skepticism According to Williamson
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
12. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 70 > Issue: 2
Earl Conee The Comforts of Home
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
13. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 70 > Issue: 2
John Hawthorne Knowledge and Evidence
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
14. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 70 > Issue: 2
Stephen Yablo Prime Causation
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
15. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 70 > Issue: 2
Timothy Williamson Replies to Commentators
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
critical notices
16. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 70 > Issue: 2
Michael J. Zimmerman Deontic Morality and Control
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
17. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 70 > Issue: 2
Frederick F. Schmitt Social Empiricism
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
18. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 70 > Issue: 2
Michael Gorr A Theory of Freedom: From the Psychology to the Politics of Agency
view |  rights & permissions | cited by