Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Browse by:



Displaying: 1-18 of 18 documents


articles
1. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 67 > Issue: 2
Stephen Laurence, Eric Margolis Concepts and Conceptual Analysis
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Conceptual analysis is undergoing a revival in philosophy, and much of the credit goes to Frank Jackson. Jackson argues that conceptual analysis is needed as an integral component of so-called serious metaphysics and that it also does explanatory work in accounting for such phenomena as categorization, meaning change, communication, and linguistic understanding. He even goes so far as to argue that opponents of conceptual analysis are implicitly committed to it in practice. We show that he is wrong on all of these points and that his case for conceptual analysis doesn’t succeed. At the same time, we argue that the sorts of intuitions that figure in conceptual analysis may still have a significant role to play in philosophy. So naturalists needn’t disregard intuitions altogether.
2. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 67 > Issue: 2
Olli Koistinen Spinoza’s Proof of Necessitarianism
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
This paper consists of four sections. The first section considers what the proof of necessitarianism in Spinoza’s system requires. Also in the first section, Jonathan Bennett’s (1984) reading of 1p16 as involving a commitment to necessitarianism is presented and accepted. The second section evaluates Bennett’s suggestion how Spinoza might have been led to conclude necessitarianism from his basic assumptions. The third section of the paper is devoted to Don Garrett’s (1991) interpretation of Spinoza’s proof. I argue that Bennett’s and Garrett’s interpretations of Spinoza’s necessitarianism have shortcomings which justify an attempt to offer an alternative proof. In the proof given in the fourth section, it is argued that Spinoza derived necessitarianism from the conjunction of the following principles: (i) necessary existence of the substances; (ii) substance-property ontology; (iii) superessentialism; and (iv) the ‘no shared attribute’ thesis.
3. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 67 > Issue: 2
Lilli Alanen What Are Emotions About?
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
This paper discusses the interrelations between three aspects of human emotions: their intentionality, their expressivity and their moral significance. It distinguishes three kinds of philosophical views of emotions: the cognitivist (classically held by the Stoics), the emotivist which reduces emotions to non-intentional bodily sensations and physiological states, and the moral phenomenologist, the latter being held by Annette Baier, whose work is the focus of the discussion. Her view, which represents an original development of ideas found in Descartes and Hume, avoids the reductionism of congitivist and emotivist accounts. The paper gives special attention to her notion of ‘deep’ objects of emotions and to her account of the expressivity of emotions, arguing that while the first is problematic, the second is a significant contribution to our understanding of the role of emotions in our moral lives.
4. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 67 > Issue: 2
Gideon Yaffe Indoctrination, Coercion and Freedom of Will
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Manipulation by another person often undermines freedom. To explain this, a distinction is drawn between two forms of manipulation: indoctrination is defined as causing another person to respond to reasons in a pattern that serves the manipulator’s ends; coercion as supplying another person with reasons that, given the pattern in which he responds to reasons, lead him to act in ways that serve the manipulator’s ends. It is argued that both forms of manipulation undermine freedom because manipulators track the compliance of their victims, while neutral causal mechanisms do not. Manipulators see to it that their victims comply even in the face of forces that threaten to derail them from the manipulator’s desired course. It is suggested that this has an impact on freedom because part of what we desire in wanting to be free is the availability of forms of life very different from those we actually enjoy.
5. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 67 > Issue: 2
Manuel García-Carpintero Qualia that It Is Right to Quine
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Dennett (1988) provides a much discussed argument for the nonexistence of qualia, as conceived by philosophers like Block, Chalmers, Loar and Searle. My goal in this paper is to vindicate Dennett’s argument, construed in a certain way. The argument supports the claim that qualia are constitutively representational. Against Block and Chalmers, the argument rejects the detachment of phenomenal from information-processing consciousness; and against Loar and Searle, it defends the claim that qualia are constitutively representational in an externalist understanding of this. The core of the argument is contained in section 3. In the first part, I contrast a minimal conception of qualia, relative to which their existence is not under dispute, with the sort of view to which I will object. In the second part I set the stage by presenting the facts about (minimal) qualia on which a Dennett-like argument can be based.
6. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 67 > Issue: 2
Joseph Heath The Transcendental Necessity of Morality
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
David Gauthier tries to defend morality by showing that rational agents would choose to adopt a fundamental choice disposition that permits them to cooperate in prisoner’s dilemmas. In this paper, I argue that Gauthier, rather than trying to work out a prudential justification for his favored choice disposition, should opt for a transcendental justification. I argue that the disposition in question is the product of socialization, not rational choice. However, only agents who are socialized in such a way that they acquire a disposition of this type could acquire the capacity to use language. Given the internal connection between language and thought, this means that no agent endowed with such a disposition could rationally choose to adopt another. Thus rational reflection by moral agents upon their own fundamental choice disposition will have no tendency to destabilize it.
7. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 67 > Issue: 2
Ram Neta Skepticism, Contextualism, and Semantic Self-Knowledge
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Stephen Schiffer has argued that contextualist solutions to skepticism rest on an implausible “error theory” concerning our own semantic intentions. Similar arguments have recently been offered also by Thomas Hofweber and Patrick Rysiew. I attempt to show how contextualists can rebut these arguments. The kind of self-knowledge that contextualists are committed to denying us is not a kind of self-knowledge that we need, nor is it a kind of self-knowledge that we can plausibly be thought to possess.
discussion
8. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 67 > Issue: 2
Jonas Olson Revisiting the Tropic of Value: Reply to Rabinowicz and Rønnow-Rasmussen
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In this paper, I defend the view that the values of concrete objects and persons are reducible to the final values of tropes. This reductive account has recently been discussed and rejected by Rabinowicz and Rønnow-Rasmussen (2003). I begin by explaining why the reduction is appealing in the first place. In my rejoinder to Rabinowicz and Rønnow-Rasmussen I defend trope-value reductionism against three challenges. I focus mainly on their central objection, that holds that the reduction is untenable since different evaluative attitudes have, ontologically speaking, different objects. I grant that this may well be so, but argue that the objection is based on an unwarranted, loose reading of the notion ‘value for its own sake’. On the more reasonable strict reading, it is plausible to maintain that tropes are the sole ontological category that can properly be ascribed final value.
book symposium:
9. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 67 > Issue: 2
Jonathan Dancy Précis of Practical Reality
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
10. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 67 > Issue: 2
R. Jay Wallace Explanation, Deliberation, and Reasons
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
11. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 67 > Issue: 2
Stephen Darwall Desires, Reasons, and Causes
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
12. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 67 > Issue: 2
Christian Piller Two Accounts of Objective Reasons
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
13. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 67 > Issue: 2
Wayne A. Davis Psychologism and Humeanism
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
14. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 67 > Issue: 2
Michael Smith Humeanism, Psychologism, and the Normative Story
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
15. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 67 > Issue: 2
John Dancy Replies
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
critical notices
16. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 67 > Issue: 2
Brian Weatherson Theories of Vagueness
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
17. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 67 > Issue: 2
Richard Double Living without Free Will
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
18. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 67 > Issue: 2
Panayot Butchvarov Reality: Fundamental Topics in Metaphysics
view |  rights & permissions | cited by