articles |
21.
|
Environmental Philosophy:
Volume >
19 >
Issue: 2
Jeremy Bendik-Keymer
The Planetary Sublime:
(Part II of The Problem of an Unloving World)
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
This essay interprets Dipesh Chakrabarty’s The Climate of History in a Planetary Age in light of the European tradition of thought about the sublime. The first half of the essay stages Chakrabarty’s historiography within that tradition focusing on a critical understanding of Kant. Then, the essay considers how the trace of the sublime in Chakrabarty’s approach to planetary history is interpretable as a form of social alienation. That argument draws on the critical theory of Steven Vogel and decolonial critique. Finally, the essay considers the moods of protest as non-alienated responses to the planetary bypassing the coloniality of the sublime.
|
|
|
22.
|
Environmental Philosophy:
Volume >
19 >
Issue: 2
Urzula Lisowska
Wonder and Politics in the Anthropocene: Beyond Curiosity and Reverence
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
The paper starts from the wonderment-reverence distinction introduced by Dipesh Chakrabarty in his book The Climate of History in a Planetary Age. While Chakrabarty’s concept of the planetary as the framework for the Anthropocene is accepted, his skepticism about the political relevance of wonder(ment) in the Anthropocene is challenged. Pace Chakrabarty, the link between wonder(ment) and curiosity is severed, and wonder is instead defined through the connections to the faculties of listening and reflective judgment. As such, wonder can be relevant to politics in the Anthropocene when engaging with the planetary
|
|
|
23.
|
Environmental Philosophy:
Volume >
19 >
Issue: 2
Dipesh Chakrabarty
Splitting the Planet? A Conversation across Differences
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
|
|
|
book reviews |
24.
|
Environmental Philosophy:
Volume >
19 >
Issue: 2
Pedro Brea
Contesting Extinctions: Decolonial and Regenerative Futures
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
|
|
|
25.
|
Environmental Philosophy:
Volume >
19 >
Issue: 2
Joy Das
Environment and Belief Systems
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
|
|
|
26.
|
Environmental Philosophy:
Volume >
19 >
Issue: 2
Kevin Siefert
Blue Architecture: Water, Design, and Environmental Futures
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
|
|
|
27.
|
Environmental Philosophy:
Volume >
19 >
Issue: 2
Rachel Spratt
Decolonial Ecology: Thinking from the Caribbean World
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
|
|
|
articles |
28.
|
Environmental Philosophy:
Volume >
19 >
Issue: 1
Russell J. Duvernoy
Thinking in Crisis: Towards an Ethics of Speculation?
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
The paper critically explores tensions inherent in speculative thinking in the context of climate change. It argues that speculative thinking is not a supererogatory luxury or idle pastime, but rather an essential necessity, especially in the context of climate change. Understanding this requires becoming more aware of operative tensions of speculative practice. In particular, the paper focusses on how climate discourses intersect and engage our variable affective economies through the affect of fear and proposes two practical virtues (“speculative courage” and “contemplative attending”) to be cultivated towards a responsible practice of speculative thought in this context.
|
|
|
29.
|
Environmental Philosophy:
Volume >
19 >
Issue: 1
Christopher D. DiBona
Listening to Nature’s Voices: Human and Animal Autonomy in Hegel
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
This article reconstructs Hegel’s account of nature’s autonomy and argues for its significance for his understanding of human autonomy and the relation between nature and spirit. It argues that Hegel treats the actualization of nature’s autonomy—epitomized by the phenomena of animal voice and birdsong—as a vital component of the actualization of free human spirit. Drawing on this analysis, the article then offers an ecological gloss on Hegel’s interest in the progressive actualization of freedom in the modern world. It concludes by sketching a Hegelian account of what it might mean to listen to nature’s voices.
|
|
|
30.
|
Environmental Philosophy:
Volume >
19 >
Issue: 1
Tom Greaves
Practicing Positive Aesthetics
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
This paper rethinks positive aesthetics as a group of aesthetic practices rather than a set of doctrines or judgments. The paper begins by setting out a general approach to aesthetic practices based on Pierre Hadot’s notion of philosophical “spiritual exercises.” Three practices of positive aesthetics are then described: focusing the beauty of each thing; envisioning the beauty of everything; and allowing the beauty of all things. The paper warns against possible dangers to which each practice may fall prey, dangers that divert the practice from its perception cultivating and enhancing potential. The paper ends by drawing out key implications of this way of considering positive aesthetics for our understanding of beauty, negativity and artificiality.
|
|
|
31.
|
Environmental Philosophy:
Volume >
19 >
Issue: 1
Agustín Mercado-Reyes
The Lesser Number: On Action and Geoengineering
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
The current crises put before us alternatives of action that require decision; for example, the decision of whether to deploy or investigate SRM geoengineering to counter global warming, which is here taken as the central example. Attending to the ontological richness of value in the elements of the world, of which scientific models and thought are a very particular and limited kind, can cast a different light into the decision process, which otherwise would almost unavoidably devolve into “infernal alternatives,” as Isabelle Stengers calls them: impossible choices between two evils.
|
|
|
32.
|
Environmental Philosophy:
Volume >
19 >
Issue: 1
Gabriella Colello, Swapna Pathak, Marcos S. Scauso
Solutions for Whom and by Whom?:
Environmental Norms and Intersectional Decoloniality
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
Many actors use the norm of climate justice to fight climate change and to struggle against global inequities internationally and domestically. Despite the enormous diversity of ways in which actors have deployed ideas of climate justice, many of the policies framed within this norm sustain oppressive, silencing, and/or assimilating tendencies. Hence, this paper looks at the biases that were introduced from ideas of “sustainable development” into the discourse of climate justice. Through the cases of India and Oceania, the paper illustrates the ways in which colonial legacies of single-axis thinking and development emphasize a particular struggle at the expense of other experiences and ways of life.
|
|
|
book reviews |
33.
|
Environmental Philosophy:
Volume >
19 >
Issue: 1
Julian Evans
On the Animal Trail
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
|
|
|
34.
|
Environmental Philosophy:
Volume >
19 >
Issue: 1
Jennifer JM Luo-Liu
How to Think about the Climate Crisis: A Philosophical Guide to Saner Ways of Living
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
|
|
|
35.
|
Environmental Philosophy:
Volume >
19 >
Issue: 1
Gregory F. Tague
Metamorphoses
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
|
|
|
articles |
36.
|
Environmental Philosophy:
Volume >
18 >
Issue: 2
Christopher Cohoon
Eating the Good: Plumwood’s Trophic Extensionism
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
Plumwood’s late work articulates two intertwined “historic tasks”: re-situating “non-human life in ethical terms” and “human life in ecological terms.” Her well-known thesis of “weak panpsychism,” an explicit rival to moral extensionism, represents her primary approach to the first task. Her approach to the second task, however, is less conspicuous. My aim is to identify and develop this approach, which, I suggest, mobilizes the fraught idea of human edibility into a certain mimetic and critical mode of extensionism that I call trophic extensionism. Inverting moral extensionist logic, it extends not moral considerability to animals but literal edibility to humans. Plumwood’s trophic extensionism both revitalizes weak panpsychism—re-vealing an unexpected link between food and mind—and generates a bold new conception of food: no longer an ontological category, food becomes an ecological relation defined by epistemological vulnerability.
|
|
|
37.
|
Environmental Philosophy:
Volume >
18 >
Issue: 2
Andrew F. Smith
Symbioculture: A Kinship-Based Conception of Sustainable Food Systems
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
Symbioculture involves nurturing the lives of those in one’s ecology, including the beings one eats. More specifically, it is a kinship-based conception of food and food systems rooted in Indigenous considerations of sustainability. Relations among food sources; cultivators, distributors, and eaters; and the land they share are sustainable when they function as extended kinship arrangements. Symbioculture hereby offers salient means to resist the ecocidal, agroindustrial food system that currently dominates transnationally in a manner that responds to the urgent need—both in terms of Indigenous justice and prudence for us all—to decolonize foodways and decommodify food, food-based knowledge, and food labor.
|
|
|
38.
|
Environmental Philosophy:
Volume >
18 >
Issue: 2
Dennis Stromback
Notes on Miki Kiyoshi’s Anthropological Humanism and Environmental Ethics
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
This article argues for the importance of using Miki Kiyoshi’s anthropological humanism as a theoretical resource for confronting the unfolding ecological crisis. What makes Miki’s anthropological humanism valuable towards this end, in particular, is in the way he blends multiple theoretical discourses—particularly Nishida and Marx—which speak to the concerns espoused by Deep Ecology and Marxist approaches to environmental philosophy. Unlike other Kyoto School thinkers deployed in the service of building an environmental ethics in recent years, Miki’s philosophical work offers social-economic alternatives to the problem of capitalism within a non-dual framework that seeks to be non-dogmatic. This article will discuss how Miki’s anthropological humanism can enrich those conversations taking place within the “green” and “red” movements by providing them with insights by which to contest and overcome anthropocentric views of reality and the system of capitalism believed to be responsible for the environmental destruction we see today.
|
|
|
39.
|
Environmental Philosophy:
Volume >
18 >
Issue: 2
Don Beith
From Biomimicry to Biosophia:
Ecologies of Technology in Benyus, Oxman, Fisch, and Merleau-Ponty
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
Biomimicry promises great progress in ecological design. Advocates, hinging on the work of Janine Benyus, argue that biomimicry enhances sustainable technologies. This essay suggests conceptual and ethical improvements to biomimicry: first by considering Michael Fisch’s concept of bioinspiration through studying Neri Oxman’s Silkworm Pavilion and second, through the articulation of a new concept of biosophia, drawing on Maurice Merleau-Ponty’s late Institution and Nature lectures. His investigation of seemingly impossible proto-mimicry prior to perception discloses a deeper comportment toward biomimicry, revealing its conditions of possibility in intercorporeal expressivity. Biosophia grounds a deeper ethic of collaboration with other lifeforms.
|
|
|
40.
|
Environmental Philosophy:
Volume >
18 >
Issue: 2
Kimberly M. Dill
Three Criteria for Environmental Authenticity:
A Response to the Simulation Problem
abstract |
view |
rights & permissions
| cited by
Broadly, I endorse the view that biodiverse species and spaces warrant conservation (partially) in virtue of their power to induce epistemic (Paul 2015; Sarkar 2011), relational, and positive, psycho-physiological transformation. However, if we are (in the not-so-distant future) able to construct cross-modally replete simulations of biodiverse environments, then what reason would we have to conserve genuine, biodiverse ecosystems? In order to address this “Simulation Problem,” I argue that the authenticity of biodiverse environments matters, both in itself and insofar as authenticity plays an important psychological, cultural, personal, and epistemic role in the lives of human agents.
|
|
|