Displaying: 601-620 of 1754 documents

0.11 sec

601. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 76 > Issue: 3
Lewis S. Ford Can Thomas and Whitehead Complement Each Other?
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Two essays relating Thomas and Whitehead have recently appeared. Coming To Be by James W. Felt, S.J., modifies Thomas by replacing his substantial form with Whitehead’s notion of subjective aim, the essencein-the-making introduced by God to guide the occasion’s act of coming into being. Felt also substitutes subjective aim for matter as the means of individuation. This is one of Whitehead’s individuating principles, although a case can be made that matter (the multiplicity of past actualities as proximate matter) is another. “God and Creativity” by Stephen T. Franklin develops a reconciliation of these two ultimates by conceiving of God as the source of creativity, and seeing creativity in terms of the Thomistic esse. In my reflections on this project I explore four alternativeswith respect to the source of creativity: (a) creativity as derived from the past; (b) creativity as inherent in the present; (c) God as the source of transitional creativity (Franklin); (d) God as the source of concrescent creativity (Ford). The last two differ with respect to being’s relation to becoming. Does being undergird becoming, or does becoming bring about being, such that apart from it there would be no being? Our theory of creation depends upon this question.
602. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 76 > Issue: 3
Charles Bambach Heidegger’s Polemos: From Being to Politics
603. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 76 > Issue: 3
Janet E. Smith Catholic Bioethics and the Gift of Life
604. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 76 > Issue: 3
Gregory A. Clark Reason in Faith: On the Relevance of Christian Spirituality for Philosophy
605. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 76 > Issue: 3
Antonio Calcagno Edith Stein Gesamtausgabe
606. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 76 > Issue: 3
Brian Davies The Metaphysical Thought of Thomas Aquinas: From Finite Being to Uncreated Being
607. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 76 > Issue: 3
F.B.A. Asiedu The Elusive Face of Modern Platonism: Iris Murdoch on Anselm and the Ontological Argument
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Iris Murdoch’s Metaphysics as a Guide to Morals ranges wide over the field of Western philosophical thought. Throughout the work, Murdoch proposes and enacts a form of philosophical inquiry that she believes supports a moral philosophy based on the idea of the good. One of her attempts, partly inspired by Paul Tillich and J. N. Findlay, centers on her critique and appropriation of the structure of the so-called “ontological argument” in Anselm’s Proslogion. This study assesses Murdoch’s accomplishment and the tenability of the kind of Platonism she proposes against Anselm’s argument about the good in both the Monologion and the Proslogion. My claim is that Anselm’s conception of the good simply does not permit the kind of interpretation that Murdoch puts on the “ontological argument.”
608. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 76 > Issue: 4
Contents of Volume 76 (2002)
609. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 76 > Issue: 4
Books Received
610. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 76 > Issue: 4
Ursula Goldenbaum Spinoza’s Parrot, Socinian Syllogisms, and Leibniz’s Metaphysics: Leibniz’s Three Strategies For Defending Christian Mysteries
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
This paper intends to show the connection between the theological, logical and epistemological ideas in Leibniz’s thinking. The paper will focus on the reasons for Leibniz’s fundamental decision to defend the Christian mysteries and his three different strategies for doing so. Each of these strategies is an answer to a particular challenge: to the Socinian who claims that the mysteries are contradictory; to the mechanical philosophy which denies the possibility of the mysteries, and to Spinoza’s parrot argument which demands that we be silent when we have no comprehension. Although he had already worked out his reconciliation of the Christian mysteries with the mechanical philosophy in Mainz around 1670, Leibniz first published it only in 1710 in his Théodicée.
611. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 76 > Issue: 4
Paul Lodge Leibniz, Bayle, and Locke on Faith and Reason
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
This paper illuminates Leibniz’s conception of faith and its relationship to reason. Given Leibniz’s commitment to natural religion, we might expect his view of faith to be deflationary. We show, however, that Leibniz’s conception of faith involves a significant non-rational element. We approach the issue by considering the way in which Leibniz positions himself between the views of two of his contemporaries, Bayle and Locke. Unlike Bayle, but like Locke, Leibniz argues that reason and faith are in conformity. Nevertheless, in contrast to the account that he finds in Locke’s Essay, Leibniz does not reduce faith to a species of reasonable belief. Instead, he insists that, while faith must be grounded in reason, true or divine faith also requires a supernatural infusion of grace.
612. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 76 > Issue: 4
Maria Rosa Antognazza Leibniz and Religious Toleration: The Correspondence with Paul Pellisson-Fontanier
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
As one might expect, throughout his life Leibniz assumed an attitude of religious toleration both ad intra (that is, toward Christians of other confessions) and ad extra (that is, toward non-Christians, notably Muslims). The aim of this paper is to uncover the philosophical and theological foundations of Leibniz’s views on this subject. Focusing in particular on his epistolary exchange with the French Catholic convert Paul Pellisson-Fontanier, I argue that neither toleration ad intra nor toleration ad extra is grounded for Leibniz in indifference toward the content of revealed religion. On the contrary, Leibniz remained convinced of the objective truth of the Christian religion as it is handed down by the millennia-old tradition of the truly universal church. In his view, reasons internal to the very nature of salvation and to the conception of God and man explicitly contained in or, at least, in accord with this tradition present religious toleration as the only justifiable answer to the differences among religions.
613. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 76 > Issue: 4
Abbreviations to Leibniz’s Works
614. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 76 > Issue: 4
Michael J. Murray Leibniz’s Proposal for Theological Reconciliation among the Protestants
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Between 1701 and 1705 Leibniz focused on the task of securing theological reunion between Lutherans and Calvinists, the two major Protestant sects at the time. Doing so, he believed, required reconciliation on two key topics, namely, the doctrine of the Eucharist, and the doctrine of election. To bring unity on the second issue, Leibniz composed a lengthy treatise based on a commentary on the Thirty-nine articles of the Church of England. This treatise stakes out a position springing from Leibniz’s own views. In this essay, I examine the views Leibniz defends in this treatise. I show that Leibniz’s views are much friendlier to the Arminian perspective than to the Calvinist one. I also show that this result is surprising since Arminian views seem incompatible with views on freedom and the problem of evil standardly attributed to Leibniz. This lack of fit should compel a re-examination of these standard attributions.
615. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 76 > Issue: 4
Jean-Pascal Anfray God’s Decrees and Middle Knowledge: Leibniz and the Jesuits
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
During the seventeenth century, disputes over middle knowledge centered on the following question: does God know contingent states of affairs before He decrees to bring them about (the Jesuit view); or, conversely, does He know them after He has decreed which states of affairs He will bring about (the Dominican view)? This article intends to cast some light on Leibniz’s view of this question. Of central importance here is the notion of a possible decree (designed both to ground contingency and to explain God’s knowledge). Despite his apparent proximity to the Dominican view, Leibniz maintained the prevolitional nature of God’s knowledge of contingent states of affairs. In order to establish this point, Leibniz’s view is compared to some little known developments in the theory of middle knowledge.
616. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 76 > Issue: 4
Donald Rutherford Introduction: Leibniz and Religion
617. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 76 > Issue: 4
Mark Kulstad Exploring Middle Ground: Was Leibniz’s Conception of God ever Spinozistic?
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Robert M. Adams has recently and controversially discussed the question whether Leibniz’s conception of God was ever Spinozistic. His affirmative answer has been opposed by Christia Mercer but supported by the present author. In this paper the debate is briefly sketched as a preliminary to the presentation of a new middle position, one that incorporates elements of both of the opposing interpretations. Along the way, the paper discusses Leibniz’s interesting treatment of God as the one and the all, as both the unity and the multiplicity in the world, and as the key to universal harmony.
618. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 76 > Issue: 4
Christia Mercer Leibniz on Knowledge and God
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Scholars have long noted that, for Leibniz, the attributes or Ideas of God are the ultimate objects of human knowledge. In this paper, I go beyond these discussions to analyze Leibniz’s views about the nature and limitations of such knowledge. As with so many other aspects of his thought, Leibniz’s position on this issue—what I will call his divine epistemology—is both radical and conservative. It is also not what we might expect, given other tenets of his system. For Leibniz, “God is the easiest and the hardest being to know.” God is the easiest to know, in that to grasp some property of an essence is to attain a knowledge of the divine essence, but God is also the most difficult to know, in that “real knowledge” of the divine essence is not available to finite beings. There is an enormous gap between the easy and the real knowledge of God, but for Leibniz, this gap is a good thing, since the very slowness of our epistemological journey prepares us morally for its end.
619. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 77 > Issue: 1
Thomas V. Upton Aristotle on Monsters and the Generation of Kinds
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
In this paper I present an interpretation of a phrase used throughout Aristotle’s Metaphysics: “man begets man.” Basing my interpretation on Aristotle’s account of the generation of animals in general and of monsters (terata) in particular, I argue that the universal genus and the universal species have causal roles to play in the generation of animals. Because the movements in the male sperm of the universal species and the universal genus (though the species and genus do not exist separately) are real, and are actual, not potential, movements, I maintain that the roles of these universals normally precede the further particularization of the developing embryo by the movements in the sperm of the particular father. I show that the roles of the movements of the genus and species are most clear in the case of the generation of monsters. I believe that the often neglected topic of the generation of monsters has important implications for Aristotle’s view of metaphysics and scientific demonstration.
620. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 77 > Issue: 1
Mark D. Gossiaux Thomas Aquinas and Giles of Rome on the Existence of God as Self-Evident
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Thomas Aquinas holds that the existence of God is self-evident in itself (because God’s essence is his existence) but not to us (since we do not know the divine essence). Giles of Rome agrees with the first part of Thomas’s claim, but he parts company with Aquinas by maintaining that God’s existence is self-evident to the wise. Since the wise can know that God is his existence, they cannot think of him as not existing. This paper reexamines Thomas’s teaching in the light of Giles’s criticisms. By examining closely what is involved in the claim that God’s essence is his existence, and how one’s knowledge of this claim is related to the knowledge that God exists, it argues that Thomas’s position has the resources to withstand Giles’s objections.