Displaying: 621-640 of 1754 documents

0.07 sec

621. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 77 > Issue: 1
James McEvoy Too Many Friends or None at All? A “Difference” Between Aristotle and Postmodernity
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Diogenes Laertius preserved a saying of Aristotle, “He who has friends can have no true friend.” This was mistranslated by Erasmus and gave rise to the words Montaigne attributed to Aristotle, “O mes amis, il n’y a nul amy.” Kant and Nietzsche both used the saying in this sense, which is in fact a contresens. The original Greek words carried much of the sense of ancient friendship, being a warning against polyphilia and a reminder that intimacy is the central value of friendship. This meaning was turned upside down to become an emblem of the lonely subject at the core of modernity.
622. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 77 > Issue: 1
Michael J. Cholbi Contingency and Divine Knowledge in Ockham
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Ockham appeared to maintain that God necessarily knows all true propositions, including future contingent propositions, despite the fact that such propositions have determinate truth values. While some commentators believe that Ockham’s attempt to reconcile divine omniscience with the contingency of true future propositions amounts to little more than a simple-minded assertion of Ockham’s Christian faith, I argue that Ockham’s position is more sophisticated than this and rests on attributing to God a dual knowledge property: God not only knows every true proposition, but knows its modal properties as well. Future contingent propositions are determinately true when actualized, not timelessly, and God’s knowledge of their truth values is knowledge of when the truth value of a proposition is actually determined.
623. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 77 > Issue: 1
Stephen Fields, S.J. The Singular as Event: Postmodernism, Rahner, and Balthasar
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Postmodernism’s unifying theme of the absent center raises an important question for metaphysics done in the Catholic tradition. Is novelty a “totally other” that utterly eludes human knowing? In posing this question, postmodernism spurs this tradition on to consider afresh how it integrates novelty and contingency. The following study concludes that no adequate account of this integration is possible without a rich concept of the singular. Rahner’s and Balthasar’s metaphysics of the singular shows that contingency, far from being an impasse to a deeper penetration into reality, is the heart of creative process in both human and non-human events. Rahner’s doctrine of substance and Balthasar’s doctrine of analogy deconstruct the relativism in postmodernism’s view of the singular, even as they develop a more extensive view of the singular for which some strains of postmodernism seem instinctively to be groping.
624. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 77 > Issue: 1
Janice L. Schultz-Aldrich Revisiting Aquinas on “Naturalism”: A Response to Patrick Lee
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
This article defends as correct and as faithful to Aquinas’s thought the tenets of “descriptivism” (sometimes called “naturalism”) in the context of criticisms that Patrick Lee has made in “Is Thomas’s Natural Law Theory Naturalist?” (American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 71:4 [1997]: 567–87). “Revisiting Aquinas” argues that evaluative utterances are descriptive; so even if human goods were immediately known by practical reason (a position nonetheless rejected), their understanding would be a descriptive one, which moral objectivity requires. The arising of the prescriptivity of precepts in relation to practical reason is then treated. The descriptivism articulated in this paper supports Lee’s emphasis on the primacy of love and choice; it further stresses that submission to an understood order of objective goods is essential to willing well.
625. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 77 > Issue: 1
Michelle Boulous Walker Driven Back to the Text: The Premodern Source of Levinas’s Postmodernism
626. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 77 > Issue: 1
Thomas Ewens Phenomenology and Lacan on Schizophrenia After the Decade of the Brain
627. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 77 > Issue: 1
Michael Harrington Vom Einen Zum Vielen: Texte des Neoplatismus im 12. Jahrhundert
628. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 77 > Issue: 1
Mary Beth Ingham, C.S.J. World as Word: Philosophical Theology in Gerard Manley Hopkins
629. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 77 > Issue: 1
John A. Laumakis Weisheipl’s Interpretation of Avicebron’s Doctrine of the Divine Will: Is Avicebron a Voluntarist?
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
In his interpretation of Avicebron’s doctrine of the divine will, Weisheipl claims that Avicebron is a voluntarist because he holds that God’s will is superior to God’s intelligence. Yet, by reexamining his Fons vitae, I argue that Avicebron is not a voluntarist. For, according to Avicebron, God’s will can be considered in two ways—(1) as inactive or (2) as active—and in neither case is God’s will superior to God’s intelligence. I conclude by noting that if, as Weisheipl contends, Avicebron—and not Augustine—was the source of the voluntarism that characterized thirteenth-century Augustinianism, that was the case only because thirteenth-century Christian thinkers misunderstood—as Weisheipl has—Avicebron’s doctrine of the divine will. For, in fact, Avicebron is not a voluntarist.
630. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 77 > Issue: 1
Books Received
631. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 77 > Issue: 2
Books Received
632. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 77 > Issue: 2
Patrick Toner Fashionable Nihilism: A Critique of Analytic Philosophy
633. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 77 > Issue: 2
Ann A. Pang-White Augustine, Akrasia, and Manichaeism
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
This paper examines Augustine’s analysis of the possible causes of akrasia and suggests that an implicit two-phased consent process takes place in an akratic decision. This two-phased consent theory revolves around Augustine’s theory of the two wills, one carnal and the other spiritual. Without the help of grace, the fallen will dominated by the carnal will can only choose to sin. After exploration of this two-phased consent theory, the paper turns to examine the accusation made by Julian of Eclanum, a fifth-century Pelagian, and J. Van Oort, a contemporary Augustinian scholar, that Augustine’s doctrine of the two wills and concupiscence led the Church into a Manichaean position. The paper concludes that this accusation fails to hold up, especially when one considers the more nuanced view on the human body and concupiscence in Augustine’s later works.
634. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 77 > Issue: 2
Alicia Finch The Empirical Stance
635. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 77 > Issue: 2
D.W. Hadley John Scottus Eriugena
636. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 77 > Issue: 2
Paul Richard Blum Istoriar la figura: Syncretism of Theories as a Model of Philosophy in Frances Yates and Giordano Bruno
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Syncretism is a challenge to modern philosophy, but it was the main characteristic of Giordano Bruno’s thought. This has been made clear by Frances A. Yates, who in interpreting Bruno and Renaissance Hermeticism was not afraid of connecting theories and cultural expressions which on the surface are alien to philosophy. In doing so Yates was congenial to her object of study, as syncretism of theory was no mere side effect of Hermeticism, but had a philosophical aim. This aim can be identified as the desire to connect the world and its general principle, as well as the powers of the human mind, into a philosophical narrative which strives at unifying oppositions and contradictions.
637. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 77 > Issue: 2
C. Jeffrey Kinlaw Schelling’s Original Insight: Schelling on the Ontological Argument and the Task of Philosophy
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
This paper concerns the way in which the transition from negative to positive philosophy is executed in Schelling’s critique of modern philosophy. Schelling’s original insight is that the transition occurs within negative philosophy by means of a twofold experience within philosophical reflection: (1) recognizing the failure of the idealist project of the conceptual determination of Being, and (2) the reversal of the idealist conception of the relation between concepts and their objects. I argue that Schelling uses a form of the ontological argument, focusing on Anselm’s formula aliquid, quo nihil maius cogitari potest, both in his critique of traditional formulations of the argument and to navigate the transition to positive philosophy.
638. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 77 > Issue: 2
John O’Callaghan More Words on the Verbum: A Response to James Doig
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
In “Verbum Mentis: Theological or Philosophical Doctrine?” (Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association, vol. 74, 2000), I argued against a common interpretation of Aquinas’s discussion of the verbum mentis. The common interpretation holds that the verbum mentis constitutes an essential part of Aquinas’s philosophical psychology. I argued, on the contrary, that it is no part of Aquinas’s philosophical psychology, but is a properly theological discussion grounded in the practice of scriptural metaphor, exemplified by such metaphors as “Christ is a rock.” James Doig challenges my alternate interpretation. His argument has three parts. He insists, first, that the discussion of the verbum mentis was a philosophical discussion in Aquinas’s predecessors, and that Aquinas never rejected this tradition; second, that it appears as a philosophical discussion in Aquinas’s commentary on the Gospel of John; third, that in the Summa theologiae, while there is no philosophical reason for Aquinas to discuss the verbum mentis in the context of the essence, powers, and operations of the soul (Ia, qq. 75–89), it is nevertheless a philosophical discussion in the examination of thedivine Trinity (Ia, qq. 27–43) Here I respond to and argue against all three legs of Doig’s counterargument.
639. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 77 > Issue: 2
Rod Coltman The Cambridge Companion to Gadamer
640. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 77 > Issue: 2
Luigi Caranti Kant und das Problem des metaphysischen Idealismus