Displaying: 441-460 of 494 documents

0.033 sec

441. Environmental Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 1
Anna Myers Melancholic Joy: On Life Worth Living
442. Environmental Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 1
Chandler D. Rogers The Imaginary of Animals
443. Environmental Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 1
Lanbin Feng Thinking Like an Iceberg
444. Environmental Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 1
Shoshana McIntosh Ways of Being Alive
445. Environmental Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 1
Lewis Rosenberg A Black Forest Walden: Conversations with Henry David Thoreau and Marlonbrando
446. Environmental Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 1
Ben Larsen Wild Diplomacy: Cohabiting with Wolves on a New Ontological Map
447. Environmental Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 1
Isabelle Bishop Loving Orphaned Space: The Art and Science of Belonging to Earth
448. Environmental Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 1
Monika Kaup Indigenous Eco-Apocalypticism: Davi Kopenawa and Bruce Albert’s The Falling Sky
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Davi Kopenawa and Bruce Albert’s 2010 collaborative work, The Falling Sky: Words of a Yanomami Shaman, centers on a prophetic warning of impending apocalyptic collapse due to anthropogenic environmental destruction. An indigenous contribution to the contemporary burst of eco-apocalyptic writing and the search for a new ecological social order, The Falling Sky challenges the temporal vector of Euroamerican eco-apocalypticism. Instead of the teleological axis of anthropocentric temporality (the emergence of homo sapiens as the pinnacle of evolution), it refers us to a temporality of terrestrial life, where homo sapiens is just one more living species in the web of life.
449. Environmental Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 1
Jayson Jimenez Becoming-Bonsai, Becoming-Carer
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
This essay reflects on my academic work and personal experience as a bonsai enthusiast. Specifically, I plan to point out how Deleuzian theory informs my bonsai practice. First, I situate bonsai gardening as an encounter with the vegetal world. Then I consider this encounter as a form of Deleuzian becoming. Becoming reifies a transformation of the two species to become another version of itself—one that occurs between a bonsai and its carer. As a bonsai carer myself, I find becoming as a precise illustration of my relationship with bonsais; hence, a vegetal encounter in the making.
450. Environmental Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 1
Olli Pitkänen Environmental Philosophy, Esotericism, and Disenchantment: A Comment on Sean McGrath’s Ecophilosophy
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Sean McGrath has produced an interesting interpretation of Renaissance Hermeticism in the context of environmental philosophy. By recovering this esoteric current he combines deep ecological criticism of anthropocentrism with humanistic critique of one-sidedly ecocentric views. After summarizing McGrath’s position and arguing for its profound potential, I will point out a problem in McGrath’s use of one of his key conceptions: disenchantment. Countering McGrath, I argue that the conception of disenchantment is not suitable for distinguishing overly ideological or superficial forms of esotericism from those with actual philosophical and political potential.
451. Environmental Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 1
Simon Nørgaard Iversen A Hegelian Perspective on Nature Recognition
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Recent posthuman theories of nature recognition seek to move beyond Hegel’s anthropological starting point. This article serves as a critical rejoinder to such posthuman attempts by taking aim at posthumanism’s flat ontology and concept of agency. Instead, it is suggested that a genuine Hegelian starting point is better suited to discern the complex interrelationship between the human and nonhuman. It is argued that a Hegelian theory of recognition that takes Hegel’s Philosophy of Nature and Philosophy of Mind into consideration can give nature its due while simultaneously preserving humans as the primary locus of agency in answering current environmental problems.
452. Environmental Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 1
Michael J. Reno Adorno on the Possibility of Nature
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
I present an interpretation of Adorno’s concept of nature that prompts a confrontation with both the domination of nature and the romanticization of nature. This interpretation would situate a normative stance toward human engagement with nature not in the idealization of a pre-social or pre-human nature, but in the (missed) possibilities of past human engagements with non-human nature. Experience of art, such as Edward Burtynsky’s photography, can push us toward such a stance. This stance forces a reconsideration of the dominant form of self-preservation in most contemporary societies; nature cannot be realized until our species understands itself as a species.
453. Environmental Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 1
Ana Vieyra Naturalizing Value and Hegel’s Notion of the Impotence of Nature
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
In this paper I suggest an alternative reading of the value of Hegel’s systematic approach to nature from the perspective of environmental philosophy. Taking the paradigmatic example of the “new materialist” ontologies, I present the problems with an inflationary justification for the argument for the need of a shift in the “scientific” representation of nature. On the basis of these problems, I suggest that Hegel’s view of nature as axiologically impotent sheds light into why emancipatory environmental theory needs not hinge on a determinate understanding of nature. In my reading, this rejection can be harmonized with the asymmetric nature of our responsibility towards non-human nature.
454. Environmental Philosophy: Volume > 1 > Issue: 1
Robert Chapman Crowded Solitude: Thoreau on Wildness
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Wilderness and wildness are not related isomorphically. Wildness is the broader category; all instances of wilderness express wildness while all instances of wildness do not express wilderness. There is more than a logical distinction between wildness and wilderness, and what begins as an analytic distinction ends as an ontological one. A more rhetorical representation of this confusion is captured by the notion of synecdoche, where, in this case, wilderness the narrower term is used for wildness the more expansive term. Although this might seem obvious at first glance, I contend that the two concepts are often misused taken as synonyms thus equivocally, setting back the cause of conceptual clarity in environmental philosophy in general, and environmental restoration in particular. One notable outcome has been the unfortunate dichotomy between preservation and conservation resulting in policy choices that needlessly deny integrated alternatives by illicit exclusion. This paper will clarify this confusion by demonstrating instances where the two concepts have been systematically abused—conflated—and show how Henry David Thoreau saw them as importantly separable. Finally, a clearer understanding of the distinctions between the two concepts provides the basis for a viable program of restoration based on an ethics of place.
455. Environmental Philosophy: Volume > 1 > Issue: 1
Ingrid Leman Stefanovic, Kenneth Maly EDITORIAL PREFACE: Environmental Philosophy
456. Environmental Philosophy: Volume > 1 > Issue: 1
Bruce Martin Wilderness and the Sacred: The Meeting of Spirit and Nature in Human Experience
457. Environmental Philosophy: Volume > 1 > Issue: 1
W. S. K. Cameron Heidegger’s Concept of the Environment in Being and Time
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Heidegger’s characterization of Dasein as Being-in-the-world suggests a natural relation to environmental philosophy. Among environmentalists, however, closer inspection must raise alarm, both since Heidegger’s approach is in some senses inescapably anthropocentric and since Dasein discovers its environment through its usability, serviceability, and accessibility. Yet Heidegger does not simply adopt a traditionally modern, instrumental view. The conditions under which the environment appears imply neither that the environment consists only of tools, nor that what is true of the parts is also true of the whole, nor that an orientation to use—where appropriate—precludes any other orientation. Heidegger’s anthropocentric commitments thus do not rule out the possibility of a non-instrumental perspective on the natural world.
458. Environmental Philosophy: Volume > 1 > Issue: 1
W. S. K. Cameron Nature by Design: People, Natural Process, and Ecological Restoration
459. Environmental Philosophy: Volume > 1 > Issue: 1
Kenneth Maly The Role of “Philosophy” in “Environmental Studies” or Why “Environmental Studies” Needs “Philosophy”
460. Environmental Philosophy: Volume > 1 > Issue: 1
Report on Books