Displaying: 441-460 of 942 documents

0.109 sec

441. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 40
Nuno Pereira Castanheira Ser Humano Desalojado: Para Uma Compreensão da Crise “Ecológica”
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
According to the United Nations, human intervention in nature set loose a series of transformations on the Earth’s ecosystems, resulting in a serious disruption of their natural balance. Some of these changes are irreversible and threaten all life on Earth, human life included. On the other hand, the world’s sociopolitical situation also seems to have reached a dead end, with millions of people living in poverty, unemployed, undernourished, and on flight from conflict. The purpose of this paper is to show how Hannah Arendt’s thought on beginnings, crisis, understanding, meaning and human existence can illuminate and inspire an attempt to retrace the origins of this “ecological” crisis, understood as the human being’s inability to be at home in the world.
442. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 40
António Queirós Campos de Deméter: Da Impossibilidade de Separar a Ciência, a Ética e a Estética na Hermenêutica da Paisagem
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Central conceptual terms, such as ‘culture’, ‘environment’, ‘nature’ and ‘landscape’, are far from being neutral scientific objects. They are academic constructions which need to be understood in their emergence across their historic contexts. Morality is a cultural expression determined by social domination and historical context, which gives it a sectary character. We need a moral theory that can be universal, timeless and that is able to guide the individual conduct, science and political ideologies, without considering the man the zenith of Life. Life, with its biodiversity, is only the tip of a complex Cosmos evolution, but we don’t know if our species, bom on planet Earth, are the final link in the Cosmos evolution. To answer all these questions, a new ethical perspective was born, a theory built upon the principles of meta-ethics and applicable to all human activities. Environmental ethics are supported by two principles - the critique against anthropocentrism and the critique against ethnocentrism, giving a universal answer to the macro moral problems of our era - environmental, social, economical and political crisis, war and weapons of mass destruction... And contributes towards rebuilding the human activities in all domains of individual and social life.
443. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 40
Francisco Teixeira Educação Ambiental: Um Itinerário Persistente e Crítico de Expansão de Cidadania
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
The aim of this article is to disclose the historical evolution of the concept and practice of Environmental Education through the study of its national and international roots, essential elements, principles and respective dimensions. The persistent processes of its ‘re-conceptualization’, within global environmental (public) policy, and the inherent ethical dimension of the environmental education towards sustainability are also challenges here necessarily taken into consideration.
444. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 40
Victor Gonçalves Foucault e a Filosofia
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Michel Foucault was a persistent, although sui generis, reader of Kant, and that is the appropriation that we will analyse. We will Start by the extensive introduction that he has made for his translation of Anthropologie in pragmatischer Hinsicht, where he shows the failure of the kantian pragmatic anthropology. We will proceed with the study of the kantian criticism in Les Mots et les Choses, which set the conditions to the transition of the Classic to the Modem episteme, allowing nevertheless, and simultaneously, the creation of a new metaphysics out of the representations and forming a philosophy obsessed by man, by means of reducing his field of knowledge to the “empiricisms” of life, of language and of work. Nietzsche will come in his help by offering, with the “disappearance of man”, the promise of the renaissance of philosophy. Finally, in a third part, we will reflect on the way Foucault commits himself more directly to the Kantian reception, by enlarging and renewing it through the importance he gave to the “diagnosis of actuality” and to the “ontology of ourselves”, instead o f the “analytics of truth”, as well as to the axiology of revolution. This was already present in the texts he wrote in the 80’s about Was ist Aufklärung? and Der Streit der Facultäten, there defining much of his own condition as a public and private thinker.
445. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 40
Informações
446. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 20 > Issue: 40
Gabriel Albiac Voz de um Maestro: Oswaldo Market
447. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 21 > Issue: 41
Adriana Veríssimo Serrão Editorial
448. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 21 > Issue: 41
José Barata-Moura Stirner: da Nadificação ao Momento Ético da Intimidade Proprietária
449. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 21 > Issue: 41
Maurice Schuhmann Max Stirner’s Critiques of Pierre-Joseph Proudhon
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Very early on, the works and ideas of the French socialist P.J.-Proudhon were discussed in the circle of the German young Hegelians. Also, Max Stimer mentioned him several times in Der Einzige und sein Eigentum. His critique of Proudhon’s thoughts is very important for his own définition and confrontation with the concept of property. The article analyses the different levels of his examination with this concept.
450. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 21 > Issue: 41
Gerhard Senft Max Stirner e a Crítica da Economia Política
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Commonly known as Max Stimer, Johann Caspar Schmidt attained considerable recognition as pedagogue and culture critic, but most of all as a philosopher of the German Vormärz. However, it is a less known fact that Stimer was also a translator and publisher of important works in the domain of economy, an activity in which he distinguished himself for being a profound connoisseur of literature on economie theory of his own time.
451. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 21 > Issue: 41
José Manuel Teixeira da Silva Liberdade de Imprensa, Censura e Dominação na Crítica de Max Stirner
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Freedom of the press is one of the most visible comerstones of a Democratic State, as well as a consensual requisite for it. Nevertheless, for Max Stirner, this gesture of demanding so cherished by political liberalism is the very negation of freedom. Freedom is neither a gift nor a concession or permission granted by the State. Freedom of the press only becomes accessible through conquest and appropriation, becoming the individual ownership as it is claimed by him. Nowadays, everyone in the developed world has at his disposal the force and means to become the owner of the freedom of the press, as Max Stimer stated. More than two centuries after Stimer’s claim, Publishing in the interactive web meets the conditions established by him for a full exercise of the freedom of press.
452. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 21 > Issue: 41
Adriana Veríssimo Serrão A Pergunta de Feuerbach a Stirner: “Que Significa ‘Ser um Indivíduo’?”
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
A complex controversy, the debate between Max Stimer and Ludwig Feuerbach is certainly one of the most interesting in the history of Contemporary ideas and surpasses, by the fruitfulness contained therein, the short time period in which it unfolded. The article considers the controversy in a particular aspect: the understanding of the category of the individual, showing the incompatibility between Unique-individual (Stimer) and the individual as being in relation (Feuerbach).
453. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 21 > Issue: 41
Bernd Kast Die Gesetzlosigkeit und Eigengesetzlichkeit Stirners ud Simmels Individuelles Gesetz: Stirners Einfluss auf Simmel und Dessen Stirner-Rezeption
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
In most of his published works, Georg Simmel dealt with themes which were also motives of concem for Stimer, such as the One and society, the individual and genre, social formations and domination, the problem of duty, egoism versus communism. Contradictions and parallelisms to Stimerian motifs can be found in Simmel’s thought since its early stages. Starting with an analysis of whether or not these are direct references to Stimer, this paper intends to show the relation between these thinkers and the possibility of a direct influence on Simmel by Stimer, namely in regards to their common idea of “individual law”.
454. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 21 > Issue: 41
Frank Hansel “Wie Hast Du’s Mit der Religion?” Religionstheorie Und -Kritik Nach Stirner
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Well before Friedrich Nietzsche had Max Stirner with great Gestus shouted (spelled) out the death of God and pulled away the veil of the realm of spirits. Religion critique after Stirner, which follows a clarified Enlightenment, can thereafter for all intents and purposes be only of two sorts: On the one hand, to explain how mankind (has) created its’ Religion and its’ Gods: Gunnar Heinsohn settles this. And on the other hand to point out: Which functional equivalents are themselves found as (religious) beliefs of humankind - freely adapted from Feuerbach: The truth of Religion is the need for it. The free self after Stirner, that knows rationally of the non-existence of God, chooses for itself its’ own respective God, or, it being strong enough, can leave it also as is.
455. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 21 > Issue: 41
Beate Kramer Stirner - On the Brink of Scientific Thought
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Stimer and Feyerabend, despite being historically a hundred and fifty years apart, seem to have been of the same mind in revolting against the methodological explaining of what cannot methodologically be explained. Stirner attempted an explanation in a more intuitive version, Feyerabend in a more sophisticated one. For both thinkers it is obviously important to sustain dissent with the assumption that method is the one and only vital promoter of scientific progress. They equally voice the opinion that, despite science itself producing inconsistencies as well as results, its proceedings nonetheless follow a certain rationale. But to codify a definite approach to phenomena or matter i.e. to establish a definite method for taking a look into things turns science into religion and scientists into believers. As a resuit no new insights are to be gained.
456. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 21 > Issue: 41
Manuel Cruz Ortiz de Landázuri Contemplación Humana y Placer Divino en Aristóteles
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Aristotle says in the Nicomachean Ethics that pleasure accompanies the perfect activity, doing it more desirable, and that the activity of contemplation is the most divine and pleasurable. On the other hand, he says in the Metaphysics that God’s activity is the most pleasurable, because his activity is perfect. In this article I try to study the relation between pleasure and activity in contemplation and its relation with God’s activity, in order to understand intellectual pleasure: is it possible to speak about a “spiritual” pleasure? Are there sensations which do not depend on material organs?
457. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 21 > Issue: 41
Cristian Eduardo Benavides La Libertad en el Idealismo Trascendental de Fichte Según la Lectura de Cornelio Fabro
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
The present paper aims to examine the development of Fichte transcendental idealism, studying particularly his notion of freedom, following the reading and comments of Fichte made by the Italian philosopher Cornelio Fabro. Issues to be discussed have a defined framework: first, it will be tried to shown Fabro’s interprétation of Fichte; second, it will be gave account of Fabro’s judgment about some particular points of Fichte idealism; and finally - but indirectly - it will be shown the influence of Fichte over Fabro him self notion of freedom.
458. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 21 > Issue: 41
Ana Rita de Almeida Ferreira Do escondido. Santo Agostinho e os limites da estética
459. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 21 > Issue: 41
Daniela Noné G. Steiner & C. Ladjali, Elogio da Transmissão: O Professor e o Aluno
460. Philosophica: International Journal for the History of Philosophy: Volume > 21 > Issue: 41
Ana Mantero Um novo olhar sobre o visível, Wassily Kandinsky e Paul Klee