Search narrowed by:



Narrow search


By category:

By publication type:

By language:

By journals:

By document type:


Displaying: 121-140 of 141 documents

0.156 sec

121. Facta Philosophica: Volume > 6 > Issue: 1
Daniel Laurier Qu’est-ce qui est non-conceptuel, l’etat ou son contenu?
122. Facta Philosophica: Volume > 6 > Issue: 1
Chris Swoyer The Autonomy of Relations
123. Facta Philosophica: Volume > 6 > Issue: 1
Yakir Levin Criterial Semantics and Qualia
124. Facta Philosophica: Volume > 6 > Issue: 1
Christopher Norris Making for Truth: Some Problems with Virtue-based Epistemology
125. Facta Philosophica: Volume > 6 > Issue: 1
Volker Halbach, Holger Sturm Bealers Masterargument: ein Lehrstuck zum Verhältnis von Metaphysik und Semantik
126. Facta Philosophica: Volume > 6 > Issue: 1
Ludwig Fahrbach Die Elimination des Wissensbegriffs
127. Facta Philosophica: Volume > 7 > Issue: 1
Anne Bezuidenhout Indexicals and Perspectivals
128. Facta Philosophica: Volume > 7 > Issue: 1
Andrea Iacona, Diego Marconi Petitio Principii: What's Wrong?
129. Facta Philosophica: Volume > 7 > Issue: 1
Wolfgang Lenzen Searles verpatzte Lösung des Freiheitsproblems
130. Facta Philosophica: Volume > 7 > Issue: 1
Ned Markosian Against Ontological Fundamentalism
131. Facta Philosophica: Volume > 7 > Issue: 1
Clotilde Calabi, Alberto Voltolini Should Pride of Place be Given to the Norms? Intentionality and Normativity
abstract | view |  rights & permissions
Reasons motivate our intentions and thus our actions, justify our beliefs, ground our hopes and connect our feelings of shame and pride to our thoughts. Given that intentions, beliefs and emotions are intentional states, intentionality is strongly connected with normativity. Yet what is more precisely their relationship? Some philosophers, notably Brandom and McDowell, contend at places that intentionality is intrinsically normative. In this paper, we discuss Brandom and McDowell’s thesis and the arguments they provide for its defence. In contrast to what they hold, we argue that neither reference intentionality nor content intentionality are intrinsically normative, although at least content intentionality has normative implications. More precisely, we argue that neither species of intentionality are normative from a semantical viewpoint, because being in an intentional state is not being in a state that is semantically correct or incorrect. Nevertheless, being in a state endowed with content may be a reason for believing or acting. Thus, we argue that content intentionality has normative implications. More precisely, we argue that any content is such that, if it is the content of a state that is sensitive to reasons—as judging paradigmatically is—then it entitles the subject of that state to have further states or to act in certain ways.
132. Facta Philosophica: Volume > 7 > Issue: 1
Robert G. Hudson Managing Underdetermination Issues in Science
133. Facta Philosophica: Volume > 2 > Issue: 2
William Child Wittgenstein and Common-Sense Realism
134. Facta Philosophica: Volume > 2 > Issue: 2
Robert B. Brandom Fighting Skepticism with Skepticism: Supervaluational Epistemology, Semantic Autonomy, and Natural Kind Skepticism
135. Facta Philosophica: Volume > 2 > Issue: 2
Phil Dowe, Mitch Parsell Jung’s Concept of ‘Coincidence’
136. Facta Philosophica: Volume > 2 > Issue: 2
Max Kistler Source and Channel in the Informational Theory of Mental Content
137. Facta Philosophica: Volume > 2 > Issue: 2
Achim Stephan Naturalisierung, Reduktion und reduktive Erklärung
138. Facta Philosophica: Volume > 2 > Issue: 2
Eduard Marbach On Depicting
139. Facta Philosophica: Volume > 2 > Issue: 2
Terry Horgan, Matjaž Potrč Biobjectivism and Indirect Correspondence
140. Facta Philosophica: Volume > 2 > Issue: 2
Dean W. Zimmerman Shoemaker’s Argument for his Theory of Properties