Cover of Thought: A Journal of Philosophy
Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Displaying: 1-10 of 10 documents


issue information
1. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 5 > Issue: 4
Issue Information
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
editorial
2. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 5 > Issue: 4
Changes to the Board of Editors
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
discussion notes
3. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 5 > Issue: 4
Alex Worsnip Explanatory Indispensability and Deliberative Indispensability: Against Enoch’s Analogy
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In this note, I discuss David Enoch’s influential deliberative indispensability argument for metanormative realism, and contend that the argument fails. In doing so, I uncover an important disanalogy between explanatory indispensability arguments and deliberative indispensability arguments, one that explains how we could accept the former without accepting the latter.
4. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 5 > Issue: 4
Neal A. Tognazzini Free Will and Miracles
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
The Consequence Argument is sound only if no one has a choice about the laws of nature, and one prominent compatibilist reply to the argument—championed by David Lewis (1981)—begins by claiming that there is a sense in which we do have such a choice, and a sense in which we don’t. Lewis then insists that the sense in which we do have such a choice is the only sense required by compatibilism. Peter van Inwagen (2004) has responded that even if Lewis’s distinction between two senses of having a choice about the laws is accepted, compatibilists are still committed to the incredible view that free will requires the ability to perform miracles. In this paper, I offer a reply to van Inwagen on Lewis’s behalf.
original articles
5. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 5 > Issue: 4
J. Adam Carter, Ian M. Church On Epistemic Consequentialism and the Virtue Conflation Problem
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Addressing the ‘virtue conflation’ problem requires the preservation of intuitive distinctions between virtue types, that is, between intellectual and moral virtues. According to one influential attempt to avoid this problem proposed by Julia Driver (2003), moral virtues produce benefits to others—in particular, they promote the well-being of others—while the intellectual virtues, as such, produce epistemic good for the agent. We show that Driver’s demarcation of intellectual virtue, by adverting to the self-/other distinction, leads to a reductio, and ultimately, that the prospects for resolving the virtue conflation problem look dim within an epistemic consequentialist approach to the epistemic right and the epistemic good.
6. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 5 > Issue: 4
Daniel Giberman Indiscernibility Does Not Distinguish Particularity
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
According to the indiscernibility characterization of the distinction between particulars and universals, only and all the former have possible numerically distinct indiscernible intrinsic qualitative duplicates. It is argued here that both the sufficiency and the necessity directions are defective and that indiscernibility thus does not distinguish particularity. Against sufficiency: universals may lack intrinsic qualitative character and thus be trivially indiscernible from one another. Against necessity: pluralities of duplicate-less entities are at once duplicate-less and particular.
7. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 5 > Issue: 4
Martin Pickup Unextended Complexes
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Extended simples are fruitfully discussed in metaphysics. They are entities which are located in a complex region of space but do not themselves have parts. In this paper, I will discuss unextended complexes: entities which are not located at a complex region of space but do themselves have parts. In particular, I focus on one type of unextended complex: pointy complexes (entities that have parts but are located at a single point of space). Four areas are indicated where pointy complexes might prove philosophically useful. Unextended complexes are therefore philosophically fruitful, in much the same way as extended simples.
8. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 5 > Issue: 4
Ramiro Caso, Nicolás Lo Guercio What Bigots Do Say: A Reply to DiFranco
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Neutral Counterpart Theories of slurs hold that the truth-conditional contribution of a slur is the same as the truth-conditional contribution of its neutral counterpart. In (2015), DiFranco argues that these theories, even if plausible for single-word slurs like ‘kike’ and ‘nigger’, are not suitable for complex slurs such as ‘slanty-eyed’ and ‘curry muncher’, figurative slurs like ‘Jewish American Princess’, or iconic slurring expressions like ‘ching chong’. In this paper, we argue that these expressions do not amount to genuine counterexamples to neutral counterpart theories of slurs. We provide a positive characterization of DiFranco’s examples that doesn’t deviate from the core of those theories.
9. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 5 > Issue: 4
T. Scott Dixon, Cody Gilmore Speaks’s Reduction of Propositions to Properties: A Benacerraf Problem
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Speaks (2014) defends the view that propositions are properties: for example, the proposition that grass is green is the property being such that grass is green. We argue that there is no reason to prefer Speaks’s theory to analogous but competing theories that identify propositions with, say, 2-adic relations. This style of argument has recently been deployed by many, including Moore (1999) and King (2007), against the view that propositions are n-tuples, and by Caplan and Tillman (2013) against King’s view that propositions are facts of a special sort.We offer our argument as an objection to the view that propositions are unsaturated (non-0-adic) relations.
10. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 5 > Issue: 4
Beau Madison Mount We Turing Machines Can’t Even Be Locally Ideal Bayesians
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Vann McGee has argued that, given certain background assumptions and an ought-implies-can thesis about norms of rationality, Bayesianism conflicts globally with computationalism due to the fact that Robinson arithmetic is essentially undecidable. I show how to sharpen McGee’s result using an additional fact from recursion theory—the existence of a computable sequence of computable realswith an uncomputable limit (a Specker sequence). In conjunction with the countable additivity requirement on probabilities, such a sequence can be used to construct a specific proposition to which Bayesianism requires an agent to assign uncomputable credence—yielding a local conflict with computationalism.