Cover of Thought: A Journal of Philosophy
Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Displaying: 1-9 of 9 documents


issue information
1. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 6 > Issue: 4
Issue Information
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
discussion note
2. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 6 > Issue: 4
Carlos Soto What If All Value Were Conferred?
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
I argue that the claim that all value is conferred is incompatible with the view that the capacity to set ends is unconditionally valuable. While this objection has beenmade, I offer a rebuttal and then a counterexample to the rebuttal. I also argue that, if all value were conferred, then the Kantian notion that moral wrongness consists in a practical contradiction is undermined.
original articles
3. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 6 > Issue: 4
Rush T. Stewart Unanimous Consensus Against AGM?
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Given the role consensus is supposed to play in the social aspects of inquiry and deliberation, it is important that we may always identify a consensus as the basis of joint inquiry and deliberation. However, it turns out that if we think of an agent revising her beliefs to reach a consensus, then, on the received view of belief revision, AGM belief revision theory, certain simple and compelling consensus positions are not always available.
4. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 6 > Issue: 4
Gabriel Uzquiano Atomism and Composition
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Atomism is the thesis that every object is composed of atoms. This principle is generally regimented by means of an atomicity axiom according to which every object has atomic parts. But there appears to be a sense that something is amiss with atomistic mereology. We look at three concerns, which, while importantly different, involve infinite descending chains of proper parts and have led some to question standard formalizations of atomism and composition in mereology.
5. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 6 > Issue: 4
Alex Gregory How Verbal Reports of Desire May Mislead
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In this paper I highlight two noteworthy features of assertions about our desires, and then highlight two ways in which they can mislead us into drawing unwarranted conclusions about desire. Some of our assertions may indicate that we are sometimes motivated independently of desire, and other assertions may suggest that there are vast divergences between our normative judgements and our desires. But I suggest that some such assertions are, in this respect, potentially misleading, and have in fact misled authors such as Russ Shafer-Landau (2003), Jack Woods (2014), and Tim Scanlon (1998).
6. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 6 > Issue: 4
Teresa Marques Pejorative Discourse Is Not Fictional
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Hom and May (2015) argue that pejoratives mean negative prescriptive properties that externally depend on social ideologies, and that this entails a form of fictionalism: pejoratives have null extensions. There are relevant uses of fictional terms that are necessary to describe the content of fictions, and to make true statements about the world, that do not convey that speakers are committed to the fiction. This paper shows that the same constructions with pejoratives typically convey that the speaker is committed to racist ideologies, in contrast with fictional discourse that typically does not. The disanalogy undermines the plausibility of fictionalism about pejoratives. Moreover, the exceptions—uncommitted uses in embedded constructions—display features that conflict with Hom and May’s explanation of committed uses as conversational implicatures.
7. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 6 > Issue: 4
Jonathan Tallant Commitment in Cases of Trust and Distrust
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
There is a well-developed literature on trust. Distrust, on the other hand, has gathered far less attention in the philosophical literature (though there is a burgeoning business literature on the topic). A recent exception to that trend in the philosophical literature is Hawley (2014, 2015) who develops a unified account of both trust and distrust. My aim in this paper is to present arguments against her account of trust and distrust, though then to also suggest a patch.
8. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 6 > Issue: 4
Andrew Parisi What’s in a Name: A Response to Ramsey
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
This paper offers a response to Ramsey’s famous challenge to draw a logical, as opposed to merely syntactical, distinction between names and predicates. Three attempts to meet this challenge are considered, one from Dummett, one from Geach, and one from Brandom. It is shown that none of these adequately addresses Ramsey’s challenge. The paper concludes with a response to Ramsey that avoids the pitfalls of the other three replies. The advantage of the view proposed is that there is nothing preventing the set of sentences in consideration from consisting only of atomic sentences. The upshot of my solution is that the distinction between names and properties rests on the presence of relational predicates in a language and the validity of the structural rules of identity, contraction, and cut.
9. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 6 > Issue: 4
Simon D. Thunder Mereological Nihilism: Keeping It Simple
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
(Mereological) nihilism states that there are no composite objects—there are only sub-atomic particles such as quarks. Nihilism’s biggest rival, (mereological) universalism, posits vast numbers of composite objects in addition to the sub-atomic particles, and so nihilism appears to be the more ontologically parsimonious of the two theories. If this is the case, it’s a significant result for the nihilist: ontological parsimony is almost always thought to be a theoretical virtue, so a nihilist victory in the parsimony stakes gives us a defeasible reason to be nihilists. But things aren’t so straightforward. Karen Bennett (2009) has argued that nihilism is no more quantitatively parsimonious than universalism. Furthermore, her argument can be redirected so that it threatens the nihilist’s perceived advantage over universalism in the qualitative parsimony stakes too. I here argue that these arguments are flawed and that nihilism is indeed more quantitatively and qualitatively parsimonious than universalism.