Cover of Thought: A Journal of Philosophy
Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Displaying: 1-20 of 36 documents


issue information
1. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 7 > Issue: 4
Issue Information
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
original articles
2. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 7 > Issue: 4
Daniel Gregory The Feeling of Sincerity: Inner Speech and the Phenomenology of Assertion
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
There is a growing literature in philosophy dealing with the phenomenon of inner speech, that is, the activity of speaking to oneself in one’s mind. This paper highlights a feature of inner speech which has not yet been noticed in this literature: that there is something distinctive that it is like to make a sincere assertion in inner speech (and, indeed, in external speech). The paper then traces out two implications of this observation. The first relates to the question of how we should characterise inner speech; the second relates to the question of how inner speech may play a role in self-attributions of belief.
3. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 7 > Issue: 4
Antti Kauppinen Agency, Experience, and Future Bias
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In Reasons and Persons, Derek Parfit (1984) observed that most people are biased towards the future at least when it comes to pain and pleasure. That is, they regard a given amount of pain as less bad when it is in the past than when it is in the future, and a given amount of pleasure as less good. While Parfit (implicitly) held that this bias is rational, it has recently come under effective attack by temporal neutralists, who have offered cases that with plausible auxiliary assumptions appear to be counterexamples to the rationality claim. I’m going to argue that these cases and the rationale behind them only suffice to motivate a more limited rejection of future bias, and that constrained future bias is indeed rationally permissible. My argument turns on the distinct rational implications of action-guiding and pure temporal preferences. I’ll argue that future bias is rational when it comes to the latter, even if not the former. As I’ll say, Only Action Fixes Utility: it is only when you act on the basis of assigning a utility to an outcome that you rationally commit to giving it the same value when it is past as when it is in the future.
4. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 7 > Issue: 4
Luke Roelofs Why Imagining Requires Content: A Reply to a Reply to an Objection to Radical Enactive Cognition
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
‘Radical enactivism’ (Hutto and Myin 2013, 2017) eschews representational content for all ‘basic’ mental activities. Critics have argued that this view cannot make sense of the workings of the imagination. In their recent book (2017), Hutto and Myin respond to these critics, arguing that some imaginings can be understood without attributing them any representational content. Their response relies on the claim that a system can exploit a structural isomorphism between two things without either of those things being a semantically evaluable representation of the other. I argue that even if this claim is granted, there remains a problem for radically enactive accounts of imagining, namely that the active establishing and maintenance of a structural isomorphism seems to require representational content even if the exploitation of such an isomorphism, when established, does not.
5. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 7 > Issue: 4
Ori Simchen The Hierarchy of Fregean Senses
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
The question whether Frege’s theory of indirect reference enforces an infinite hierarchy of senses has been hotly debated in the secondary literature. Perhaps the most influential treatment of the issue is that of Burge (1979), who offers an argument for the hierarchy from rather minimal Fregean assumptions. I argue that this argument, endorsed by many, does not itself enforce an infinite hierarchy of senses. I conclude that whether or not the theory of indirect reference can avail itself of only finitely many senses is pending further theoretical development.
6. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 7 > Issue: 4
Artūrs Logins Subjective Unpossessed Reasons
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
A common assumption in contemporary debates about normative reasons is that ‘subjective’ and ‘possessed’ are two names for the same sort of reason. This paper challenges that assumption. Given our cognitive limitations, it is unsurprising that normative reasons that derive from what we know and reasons that we are in a position to use in our deliberation are not always one and the same.
7. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 7 > Issue: 4
Claudio Calosi Solving a Mereological Puzzle
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
There is an interesting puzzle about the interaction between mereology, topology, and dependence. It is not only interesting in and on itself, but also reveals subtleties about the aforementioned interaction that have gone unnoticed. The puzzle has it that the following plausible claims are jointly inconsistent: (i) wholes depend on their parts; (ii) boundaries are parts; (iii) boundaries depend on the whole they are part of. In the paper, I first argue that claims (i)–(iii) are not as a matter of fact inconsitent insofar as further assumptions are needed to get the puzzle off the ground. I consider several such assumptions, somemore plausible than others. Though I do not take any definite stance as to whether the plusibility of the assumptions considered trump that of claims (i)–(iii), I set forth a suggestion to replace (iii) with something similar yet interestingly different.
8. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 7 > Issue: 4
Al Abasnezhad, C.S.I. Jenkins Metaphysical Vagueness Without Vague Objects
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Elizabeth Barnes and Robert Williams have developed a theory of metaphysical indeterminacy, via which they defend the theoretical legitimacy of vague objects. In this paper, we argue that while the Barnes–Williams theory supplies a viable account of genuine metaphysical vagueness, it cannot underwrite an account of genuinely vague objects. First we clarify the distinction between these two key theses. Then we argue that the Barnes–Williams theory of metaphysical vagueness not only fails to deliver genuinely vague objects, it in fact provides grounds for rejecting them.
discussion note
9. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 7 > Issue: 4
Lars B. Gundersen, Eline Busck Gundersen Conjunction Conditionalization and Irrelevant Semifactuals
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Are counterfactuals with true antecedents and consequents trivially true? The principle of Conjunction Conditionalization ((A˄C)→(A>C)) is highly controversial. Many philosophers view it as an attractive feature of Lewis’s semantics for counterfactuals that it can easily be modified to avoid this principle. However, Walters and Williams (2013) beg to differ. They argue that Conjunction Conditionalization is an indispensable ingredient of any Lewisian semantics, since CC is entailed by standard Lewisian theorems and a plausible semantic claim about irrelevant semifactuals. If this is true, the entire tradition of revisionist counterfactual semantics is misguided, and so are many philosophical theories in which counterfactuals play a role. We argue, in defense of the revisionist tradition, that Walters and Williams’ ‘plausible semantic claim’ is in fact anything but plausible. It turns out to entail semantic principles far more controversial than Conjunction Conditionalization.
issue information
10. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 7 > Issue: 3
Issue Information
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
original articles
11. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 7 > Issue: 3
Justin Mooney Multilocation and Parsimony
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
One objection to the thesis that multilocation is possible claims that, when combined with a preference for parsimonious theories, it leads to the absurd result that we ought to believe the material universe is composed of just one simple particle. I argue that this objection fails.
12. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 7 > Issue: 3
Simon Thomas Hewitt Tuples all the Way Down?
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
We can introduce singular terms for ordered pairs by means of an abstraction principle. Doing so proves useful for a number of projects in the philosophy of mathematics. However there is a question whether we can appeal to the abstraction principle in good faith, since a version of the Caesar Problem can be generated, posing the worry that abstraction fails to introduce expressions which refer determinately to the requisite sort of object. In this note I will pose the difficulty, and then propose a solution. Since my solution appeals to a plausible constraint on the introduction of new expressions to a language, it is of interest independently of the particular case of terms for pairs. Since these provide the occasion for discussion we should nonetheless review the use of abstraction for pairs before the argumentative business of the paper commences.
13. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 7 > Issue: 3
Han van Wietmarschen The Colonized and the Wrong of Colonialism
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In “What’s Wrong with Colonialism,” Lea Ypi argues that the distinctive wrong of colonialism should be understood as the failure of the colonial relationship to extend equal and reciprocal terms of political association to the colonized. Laura Valentini argues that Ypi’s account fails. Her argument targets an ambiguity in Ypi’s account of the relata of the colonial relationship. Either Ypi’s view is that the members of the colonized group are, as individuals, denied an equal and reciprocal political relationship to the colonizer, or Ypi’s view is that the colonized individuals form a collective agent and that it is denied an equal and reciprocal relationship to the colonizer. According to Valentini, both options face insurmountable difficulties. This paper argues that Valentini sets up a false dilemma: the third option is to think of the colonizer as relating in an unequal and nonreciprocal way to the plurality of people subjected to colonial rule. This view, I argue, avoids Valentini’s objections, but it also raises new questions about how we are to understand the distinctive wrong of colonialism.
14. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 7 > Issue: 3
Andreas Fjellstad Infinitary Contraction-Free Revenge
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
How robust is a contraction-free approach to the semantic paradoxes? This paper aims to show some limitations with the approach based on multiplicative rules by presenting and discussing the significance of a revenge paradox using a predicate representing an alethic modality defined with infinitary rules.
15. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 7 > Issue: 3
Dustin Tucker Paradoxes and Restricted Quantification: A Non-Hierarchical Approach
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Andrew Bacon, John Hawthorne, and Gabriel Uzquiano (Bacon, Hawthorne, and Uzquiano 2016) have recently argued that free logics—logics that reject or restrict Universal Instantiation—are ultimately not promising approaches to resolving a family of intensional paradoxes due to Arthur Prior (Prior 1961). These logics encompass ramified and contextualist approaches to paradoxes, and broadly speaking, there are two kinds of criticism they face. First, they fail to address every version of the Priorean paradoxes. Second, the theoretical considerations behind the logics make absolutely general statements about all propositions, properties of propositions, etc., but because this sort of intensional quantification is always restricted in the logics, they cannot even express those considerations. I present a novel sort of free logic, which rejects the standard Universal Instantiation but validates a restricted form of the rule, and which addresses both kinds of criticism by allowing some propositions to be unrestricted in their quantification.
16. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 7 > Issue: 3
Adam Michael Bricker Do Judgements about Risk Track Modal Ordering?
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
On the standard conception of risk, the degree to which an event is risky is the function of the probability of that event. Recently, Duncan Pritchard has challenged this view, proposing instead a modal account on which risk is conceived of in terms of modal ordering (2015). On this account, the degree of risk for any given event is a function of its modal distance from the actual world, not its likelihood. Pritchard’s main motivation for this is that the probabilistic account cannot always explain our judgements about risk. In certain cases, equally probable events are not judged to be equally risky. Here I will argue that Pritchard’s account succumbs to a similar problem. Put simply, there are cases inwhich judgements about risk decouple fromboth probability andmodal ordering. Thus, if we want a theory of risk that can explain our judgements about risk, neither the probabilistic nor modal account is successful.
17. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 7 > Issue: 3
Roberto Loss Fine’s Trilemma and the Reality of Tensed Facts
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Fine (2005, 2006) has presented a ‘trilemma’ concerning the tense-realist idea that reality is constituted by tensed facts. According to Fine, there are only three ways out of the trilemma, consisting in what he takes to be the three main families of tense-realism: ‘presentism’, ‘(external) relativism’, and ‘fragmentalism’. Importantly, although Fine characterises tense-realism as the thesis that reality is constituted (at least in part) by tensed facts, he explicitly claims that tense realists are not committed to their fundamental existence. Recently, Correia and Rosenkranz (2011, 2012) have claimed that Fine’s tripartite map of tense realism is incomplete as it misses a fourth position they call ‘dynamic absolutism’. In this paper, I will argue that dynamic absolutists are committed to the irreducible existence of tensed facts and that, for this reason, they face a similar trilemma concerning the notion of fact-content. I will thus conclude that a generalised version of Fine’s trilemma, concerning both fact-constitution and fact-content, is indeed inescapable.
18. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 7 > Issue: 3
Neven Sesardić Avoid Certain Frustration—Or Maybe Not?
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In the situation known as the cable guy paradox, the expected utility principle and the avoid certain frustration (ACF) principle seem to give contradictory advice aboutwhat one should do.This article tries to resolve the paradox by presenting an example that weakens the grip of ACF: a modified version of the cable guy problem is introduced in which the choice dictated by ACF loses much of its intuitive appeal.
issue information
19. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 7 > Issue: 2
Issue Information
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
original articles
20. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 7 > Issue: 2
Johannes Stern Proving that the Mind Is Not a Machine?
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
This piece continues the tradition of arguments by John Lucas, Roger Penrose and others to the effect that the human mind is not a machine. Kurt Gödel thought that the intensional paradoxes stand in the way of proving that the mind is not a machine. According to Gödel, a successful proof that the mind is not a machine would require a solution to the intensional paradoxes. We provide what might seem to be a partial vindication of Gödel and show that if a particular solution to the intensional paradoxes is adopted, one can indeed give an argument to the effect that the mind is not a machine.