Cover of Thought: A Journal of Philosophy
Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Displaying: 1-11 of 11 documents


1. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 1 > Issue: 4
John Divers, Carrie Ichikawa Jenkins, Crispin Wright Editorial
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
original articles
2. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 1 > Issue: 4
David Ripley Response to Heck
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In Heck (2012), Richard Heck presents variants on the familiar liar paradox, intended to reveal limitations of theories of transparent truth. But all existing theories of transparent truth can respond to Heck’s variants in just the same way they respond to the liar. These new variants thus put no new pressure on theories of transparent truth.
3. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 1 > Issue: 4
Julien Murzi On Heck’s New Liar
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Richard Heck has recently drawn attention on a new version of the Liar Paradox, one which relies on logical resources that are so weak as to suggest that it may not admit of any ‘‘truly satisfying, consistent solution’’. I argue that this conclusion is too strong. Heck’s Liar reduces to absurdity principles that are already rejected by consistent paracomplete theories of truth, such as Kripke’s and Field’s. Moreover, the new Liar gives us no reasons to think that (versions of) these principles cannot be consistently retained once the structural rule of contraction is restricted. I suggest that revisionary logicians have independent reasons for restricting such a rule.
4. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 1 > Issue: 4
Richard G. Heck Jr More on ‘A Liar Paradox’
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
5. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 1 > Issue: 4
Jack Woods Failures of Categoricity and Compositionality for Intuitionistic Disjunction
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
6. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 1 > Issue: 4
Kathrin Glüer Martin on the Semantics of ‘Looks’
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
A natural way of understanding (non-epistemic) looks talk in natural language is phenomenalist: to ascribe looks to objects is to say something about the way they strike us when we look at them. This explains why the truth values of looks-sentences intuitively vary with the circumstances with respect to which they are evaluated. ButMikeMartin (2010) argues that there is no semantic reason to prefer a phenomenalist understanding of looks to ‘‘Parsimony’’, the position according to which looks are basic visible properties. He suggests a semantics for looks-sentences that explains their intuitive truth values and is compatible with Parsimony. I argue that there is semantic reason to prefer a phenomenalist understanding of looks to a parsimonious one since there is a simpler semantics compatible with a phenomenalist understanding of looks, but not with Parsimony. This semantics provides a better explanation of the relevant truth value distribution.
7. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 1 > Issue: 4
Aaron M. Griffith On Some Alleged Truthmakers for Negatives
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
This article considers three recent attempts by David Armstrong, Ross Cameron, and Jonathan Schaffer to provide truthmakers for negative existential truths. It is argued that none of the proposed truthmakers are up to the task of making any negative existential truth true and, it will turn out, for the same reason.
8. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 1 > Issue: 4
Elia Zardini It Is Not the Case that [P and ‘It Is Not the Case that P’ Is True] nor Is It the Case that [P and ‘P’ Is Not True]
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
A new semantic paradox developed by Richard Heck and relying on very minimal logical and truth-theoretic resources is rehearsed. A theory of truth restricting the structural metarule of contraction is presented and some of the theory’s relevant features are made explicit. It is then shown how the theory provides a principled solution to the paradox while preserving the extremely compelling truth-theoretic principles at stake, thus bringing out a significant advantage that the theory enjoys over virtually all other non-dialetheic theories. It is finally argued that such advantage is amplified by theoretical considerations made available by the adoption of a correspondentist perspective in the philosophy of truth.
9. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 1 > Issue: 4
Mark Jago The Problem with Truthmaker-Gap Epistemicism
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Epistemicism about vagueness is the view that vagueness, or indeterminacy, is an epistemic matter. Truthmaker-gap epistemicism is the view that indeterminate truths are indeterminate because their truth is not grounded by any worldly fact. Both epistemicism in general and truthmaker-gap epistemicism originated in Roy Sorensen’s work on vagueness. My aim in this paper is to give a characterization of truthmaker-gap epistemicism and argue that the view is incompatible with higher-order vagueness: vagueness in whether some case of the form ‘it is determinate that A’ or ‘it is indeterminate whether A’ is true. Since it is highly likely that there is higher-order vagueness (and indeed, Sorensen is adamant that there is higher-order vagueness), truthmaker-gap epistemicism is in an uncomfortable position.
10. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 1 > Issue: 4
Nikk Effingham Impure Sets May Be Located: A Reply to Cook
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Cook argues that impure sets are not located. But ‘location’ is an ambiguous word and when we resolve those ambiguities it turns out that on no resolution is Cook’s argument compelling.
11. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 1 > Issue: 4
Conor McHugh Control of Belief and Intention
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
This paper considers a view according to which there are certain symmetries between the nature of belief and that of intention. I do not defend this Symmetry View in detail, but rather try to adjudicate between different versions of it: what I call Evaluative, Normative and Teleological versions. I argue that the centralmotivation for the Symmetry View in fact supports only a specific Teleological version of the view.