Cover of Teaching Philosophy
Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Browse by:



Displaying: 1-20 of 55 documents


articles
1. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 4
Chong Choe-Smith Academic Internships in Philosophy
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Academic internships are increasingly common in other disciplines, but have not been discussed or implemented widely in the discipline of philosophy. This article fills this gap by discussing the potential benefits of philosophy internships and addressing two important questions: whether there is something different about philosophy—possibly its abstractness, versatility, or what I refer to as “pluripotency”—that renders the benefits of internships out of reach for many philosophy students, and whether philosophy faculty should be responsible for developing and implementing philosophy internships. In this article, I argue that there is nothing about the discipline itself that prevents philosophy majors from experiencing the benefits of academic internships and that, among the different possible internship coordinators, philosophy faculty bear primary responsibility for developing academic internships in philosophy and assisting philosophy students as they transition from college to professional career.
2. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 4
Lisa Gilbert Blending Synchronous and Asynchronous Discussion Strategies to Promote Community and Criticality during a Time of Crisis
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
While discussion is a hallmark of philosophy teaching methods, some instructors express doubt as to the possibilities for its meaningful implementation in online classes. Here, I report on a routine that utilized synchronous and asynchronous discussion strategies to promote community-building and critical engagement in an educational philosophy class forced online due to the COVID-19 pandemic. Before class, students used social annotation software to collaboratively read a text. During class, we pursued whole-group discussion using student-centered strategies before breaking into partners for small-group work on a written discussion prompt. After class, students individually replied to the prompts written by these small groups. Results show that students found that this routinized structure promoted engagement with the course content and each other, ultimately building a community that supported critical thinking in the virtual classroom. Implications are raised regarding instructor workload and control over course outcomes.
3. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 4
Anna Gotlib, Ruth Groenhout Fractured Epistemologies: Bioethics Pedagogy Meets Science Denialism
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
The COVID-19 pandemic and its conflict with science denialism raises the question of how philosophers teaching bioethics should respond to debates concerning truth, scientific evidence, and medical treatment raised by their students. We suggest that philosophical responses to the spread of serious disinformation in the health care context can be effectively explored in bioethics courses through discussions of informed consent, patient autonomy, the nature of scientific evidence, and moral responsibly for one’s views in ways that are especially important in the current pandemic era. Addressing these issues offers important epistemological grounding for students who will soon be making biomedical judgments and policies, as well as students who, like the rest of us, will be on the receiving end of those decisions. We argue that helping all of our students to understand the epistemological structures, and the moral consequences, of biomedicine and its detractors is a vital part of the professor’s responsibility.
4. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 4
Robert Weston Siscoe, Zachary Odermatt Seeking to Understand: Small Group Dialogues about Race and Gender
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
It is no secret that we, as a society, struggle to have productive conversations about race and gender. Discussions about these issues are beset with obstacles, from the inherent power dynamics between conversation partners to the fear that participants feel about saying something harmful. One practice that can help address these difficulties is intergroup dialogue—sustained, small group discussions with participants from a variety of social identities. In this paper, we detail how we incorporated intergroup dialogue into a 120-student “Philosophy of Race, Class, and Gender” course, providing a blueprint for anyone who wants to help their students develop the ability to take part in fruitful conversations surrounding these challenging topics. We provide strategies for how to design intergroup dialogues to avoid many of the common pitfalls of such conversations, strategies that ultimately helped our students become more likely to initiate and participate in worthwhile discussions on race and gender. We expect our experiences to be especially helpful for instructors of large courses, where making time for small group dialogue is quite challenging, but many of the practices we used can also be adapted for smaller scale courses as well.
book reviews
5. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 4
Russell W. Askren Future Morality, edited by David Edmonds
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
6. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 4
Vanessa Freerks A Continental Guide to Philosophy, by John Douglas Macready
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
7. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 4
Bertrand Guillaume Philosophy, Politics, and Economics: An Introduction, by Gerald Gaus and John Thrasher
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
8. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 4
John Kinsey Coping: A Philosophical Guide, by Luc Bovens; illustrated by Fiorella Lavado
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
9. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 4
Barry Kleinberg Human and Animal Minds: The Consciousness Question Laid to Rest, by Peter Carruthers
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
10. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 4
Cecilea Mun First-Order Logic: A Concise Introduction, 2nd edition, by John Heil
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
11. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 4
Dale Murray Pandemic Bioethics, by Gregory E. Pence
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
12. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 4
Robert C. Robinson Doing Ethics: Moral Reasoning, Theory, and Contemporary Issues, 6th edition, by Lewis Vaughn
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
13. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 4
Theordore Stone The Democracy Reader: From Classical to Contemporary Philosophy, edited by Steven M. Cahn, Andrew T. Forechimes and Robert B. Talisse
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
14. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 4
Sandra Tomsons Applied Ethics: An Impartial Introduction, by Elizabeth Jackson, Tyron Goldschmidt, Dustin Crummett, and Rebecca Chan
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
articles
15. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 3
Galen Barry Facts vs. Opinions: Helping Students Overcome the Distinction
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Many students struggle to enter moral debates in a productive way because they automatically think of moral claims as ‘just opinions’ and not something one could productively argue about. Underlying this response are various versions of a muddled distinction between ‘facts’ and ‘opinions.’ This paper outlines a way to help students overcome their use of this distinction, thereby clearing an obstacle to true moral debate. It explains why the fact-opinion distinction should simply be scrapped, rather than merely sharpened. It then proposes a different distinction well suited to replace it. Finally, it outlines an activity which can be used to teach the new distinction, as well as a number of benefits to attempting the whole replacement process.
16. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 3
C. D. Brewer Proof Golf: A Logic Game
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Here I describe a game that I use in my logic classes once we begin derivations. The game can help improve class dynamics, help struggling students recognizes they are not alone, open lines of communication between students, and help students of all levels prepare for exams. The game can provide struggling students with more practice with the fundamental rules of a logical system while also challenging students who excel at derivations. If students are struggling with particular rules or strategies in the system, the game can be tailored to address them. I explain how the game has evolved since I started using it, highlighting the pedagogical benefits of the changes I have made, and (in the appendix) I provide examples of the handouts I distribute and a “checklist” to use before, during, and after the game.
17. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 3
Thomas Metcalf The Case for Philosophy as a General-Education Requirement
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
I argue that colleges should include philosophy courses as general-education requirements. I begin by explaining the prima facie case against general-education requirements and the need for philosophers to defend their courses’ place in the general-education curriculum. Next, I present two arguments for philosophy as a general-education requirement. The first is the Argument from Content: that philosophy courses’ content tends to match the intended nature and purposes of general-education courses. The second is the Argument from Outcomes: that even if philosophy courses didn’t match the intended purposes of general-education courses, they would still be appropriate as general-education requirements, because there is empirical evidence that philosophy courses produce valuable skills and knowledge in students.
18. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 3
Jeff Mitchell On the Invidious Distinction Between Weak and Strong Critical Thinking
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
The distinction between weak and strong forms of critical thinking is a hallmark of Richard Paul’s pedagogy. He maintains that good reasoning entails a personal commitment to fair-mindedness. In this brief essay, I argue that Paul’s conception of fair-mindedness conflates cognitive empathy with empathetic concern and altruism. One’s understanding another’s perspective by no means entails approving of it, and one may seek to better grasp this standpoint for purely selfish reasons. Depending upon the circumstances, the other could be one’s competitor, enemy, mark, or even intended victim. This implies that while we may wish that the world were otherwise, even very bad people can be highly effective critical thinkers.
19. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 3
Jake Wright An Argument for Asynchronous Course Delivery in the Early Stages of the COVID-19 Pandemic
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
I argue that campus closures and shifts to online instruction in the early stages of the COVID-19 pandemic created an obligation to offer courses asynchronously. This is because some students could not have reasonably foreseen circumstances making continued synchronous participation impossible. Offering synchronous participation options to students who could continue to participate thusly would have been unfair to students who could not participate synchronously. I also discuss why ex post facto consideration of this decision is warranted, noting that similar actions may be necessary in the future and that other tough pedagogical cases share important similarities with this case.
book reviews
20. Teaching Philosophy: Volume > 45 > Issue: 3
Patrick D. Anderson Rick and Morty and Philosophy: In the Beginning Was the Squanch. Edited by Lester C. Abesamis and Wayne Yuen
view |  rights & permissions | cited by