Cover of Thought: A Journal of Philosophy
Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Displaying: 1-20 of 37 documents


issue information
1. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 9 > Issue: 4
Issue Information
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
original articles
2. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 9 > Issue: 4
Fernando Rudy-Hiller Inverse enkrasia and the real self
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Non-reflectivist real self views claim that people are morally responsible for all and only those bits of conduct that express their true values and cares, regardless of whether they have endorsed them or not. A phenomenon that is widely cited in support of these views is inverse akrasia, that is, cases in which a person is praiseworthy for having done the right thing for the right reasons despite her considered judgment that what she did was wrong. In this paper I show that non-reflectivist real self views are problematic by focusing on the related but neglected phenomenon of inverse enkrasia, which occurs when an agent commits wrongdoing by following a mistaken evaluative judgment that, unbeknownst to her, runs contrary to her true values and cares. Intuitively, inverse enkratics are blameworthy for their actions although the latter don't express their real selves; therefore, non-reflectivist real self views are false. I assess the implications of this result for the viability of the quality of will paradigm and conclude that the latter survives unscathed to the problems besetting real self views. The lesson is that defenders of the quality of will paradigm should stop talking about real selves altogether.
3. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 9 > Issue: 4
Will Fleisher Publishing without (some) belief
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
4. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 9 > Issue: 4
Bradford Saad An exclusion problem for epiphenomenalist dualism
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
The chief motivation for epiphenomenalist dualism is its promise to solve dualism's causal exclusion problem without inducing causal overdetermination or violations of the causal closure of the physical. This paper argues that epiphenomenalist dualism is itself susceptible to an exclusion problem. The problem exploits symmetries of determination and influence generated by a wide class of physical theories. Further, I argue that there is an interference effect between solving epiphenomenalist dualism's exclusion problem and using epiphenomenalist dualism as a solution to the causal exclusion problem. What emerges is an overlooked, empirically motivated challenge to epiphenomenalist dualism.
5. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 9 > Issue: 4
Henry Taylor, Bilge Sayim Redundancy masking and the identity crowding debate
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Some have claimed that identity crowding is a case where we consciously see an object to which we are unable to pay attention. Opponents of this view offer alternative explanations, which emphasise the importance of prior knowledge, amongst other factors. We review new empirical evidence showing that prior knowledge has a profound effect on identity crowding. We argue that this is problematic for the “conscious seeing without attention” view, and supports an opposing view.
6. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 9 > Issue: 4
Dominic McIver Lopes Desolation sound: Social practices of natural beauty
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Instances of natural beauty are widely regarded as counterexamples to practice-based theories of aesthetic value. They are not. To see that they are not, we require the correct account of natural beauty and the correct account of social practices.
7. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 9 > Issue: 4
Luca Barlassina Beyond good and bad: Reflexive imperativism, not evaluativism, explains valence
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Evaluativism by Carruthers and reflexive imperativism by Barlassina and Hayward agree that valence—the (un)pleasantness of experiences—is a natural kind shared across all affective states. But they disagree about what valence is. For evaluativism, an experience is pleasant/unpleasant in virtue of representing its worldly object as good/bad; for reflexive imperativism, an experience is pleasant/unpleasant in virtue of commanding its subject to get more/less of itself. I argue that reflexive imperativism is superior to evaluativism according to Carruthers's own standards. He maintains that a theory of valence should account for its phenomenology and role in imagination-based decision-making. I show that it is reflexive imperativism, rather than evaluativism, that fits this explanatory bill.
8. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 9 > Issue: 4
Thomas J. Hughes Deixis, demonstratives, and definite descriptions
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Definite articles and demonstratives share many features in common including a related etymology and a number of parallel communicative functions. The following paper is concerned with developing a novel proposal on how to distinguish the two types of expression. First, crosslinguistic evidence is presented to argue that demonstratives contain locational markers that are employed in deictic uses to force contrastive focus and accentuate an intended referent against a contextual background. Conversely, definite articles lack such markers. Demonstratives are thus more likely to force referential interpretations, whereas definite descriptions are more open to attributive ones. Second, an analysis of determiner phrases is provided to illustrate that certain syntactic projections capture deictic differences between the two expressions. Semantic correlates of the proposal are then considered before it is situated with respect to contemporary work distinguishing the two categories on the basis of a non-redundancy condition (that the overt noun phrase complement of a demonstrativemay not denote a singleton set), which I suggest is derivative on the presence of contrastive deictic markers in demonstratives.
discussion note
9. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 9 > Issue: 4
Joulia Smortchkova Does empirical evidence support perceptual mindreading?
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
According to perceptual accounts of mindreading, we can see, rather than cognize, other people's mental states. On one version of this approach, certain mental properties figure in the contents of our perceptual experiences. In a recent paper, Varga has appealed to empirical research to argue that intentions and emotions can indeed be seen, rather than cognized. In this paper, I argue that none of the evidence adduced to support the perceptual account of mindreading shows that we see mental properties, as opposed to non-mental properties.
issue information
10. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 9 > Issue: 3
Issue Information
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
original articles
11. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 9 > Issue: 3
Carlos Núñez An alternative norm of intention consistency
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In this paper, I formulate a norm of intention consistency that is immune to the kind of cases that have been put forth to argue either that rationality does not require consistency between an agent's intentions, or that, if it does, then rationality is not normative. The norm I formulate mimics refinements that have been made to the norm of means-end coherence in response to cases where, intuitively, you need not be irrational when you intend an end e, despite not intending the means m you believe to be necessary for e, because you do not believe that intending m is necessary for e. Similarly, according to the norm I put forth, if you intend e, and believe that e is inconsistent with e*, you need not be irrational if you also intend e*, as long as you do not believe that intending e* is inconsistent with e.
12. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 9 > Issue: 3
Bence Nanay Perceiving indeterminately
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
It has been argued recently that perception is indeterminate. But there are more than one ways of spelling out what this means. The standard line is that perceptual states attribute different probabilities to different propositions. I provide an alternative to this view, where it is not the attitude, but the content of perceptual states that is indeterminate, inasmuch as it consists of the representation of determinable properties. This view does justice to the more general claim that perception is indeterminate without appealing to probability either in the attitude or in the content.
13. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 9 > Issue: 3
Grace Paterson Sincerely, Anonymous
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
This paper provides an account of anonymous speech treated as anonymized speech. It is argued that anonymous speech acts are best defined by reference to intentional acts of blocking a speaker's identification as opposed to the various epistemic effects that imperfectly correlate with these actions. The account is used to examine two important subclasses of anonymized speech: speech using pseudonyms, and speech anonymized in a specifically communicative manner. Several pragmatic and ethical issues with anonymized speech are considered.
14. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 9 > Issue: 3
Alexander Gebharter Free will as a higher-level phenomenon?
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
List (2014, 2019) has recently argued for a particular view of free will as a higher-level phenomenon compatible with determinism. According to List, one could refute his account by showing that determinism at the physical level implies the impossibility of doing otherwise at the agential level. This paper takes up that challenge. Based on assumptions to which List's approach is committed, I provide a simple probabilistic model that establishes the connection between physical determinism and the impossibility of doing otherwise at the agential level that is needed to refute free will as a higher-level phenomenon.
15. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 9 > Issue: 3
Shay Allen Logan Putting the stars in the their places
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
This paper presents a new semantics for the weak relevant logic DW that makes the role of the infamous Routley star more explicable. Central to this rewriting is combining aspects of both the American and Australian plan for understanding negations in relevance logics.
16. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 9 > Issue: 3
David Turon Counterfactuals and double prevention: Trouble for the Causal Independence thesis
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Some have argued that no analysis of counterfactual conditionals can succeed without appealing to causal notions. Such authors claim that, in determining what would transpire had some events gone differently, we hold fixed everything that is causally independent from those events. Call this view Causal Independence. Some have argued that we need Causal Independence to accommodate intuitive judgments about certain kinds of counterfactuals in indeterministic worlds. The aim of this paper is to show that, contra these authors, Causal Independence systematically delivers counterintuitive results for a certain subset of such counterfactuals-namely, those involving causation by double prevention. I conclude that intuitions about such counterfactuals do not motivate Causal Independence, at least in any form in which it has thus far been articulated. However, I suggest that a refined Causal Independence thesis that presupposes a kind of causal pluralism might be able to accommodate these intuitions, though such a refined version of Causal Independence may not conflict with reductive analyses of causal notions that appeal to counterfactuals after all.
discussion notes
17. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 9 > Issue: 3
Jonny McIntosh How to understand the knowledge norm of assertion: Reply to Schlöder
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Julian Schlöder (2018) examines Timothy Williamson's proposal that knowledge is the norm of assertion within the context of deontic logic. He argues for two claims, one concerning the formalisation of the thesis that knowledge is a norm of assertion and another concerning the formalisation of the thesis that knowledge is the only norm of assertion. On the basis of these claims, Schlöder goes on to raise a series of problems for Williamson's proposal. In response, I argue that both of Schlöder's claims can—and should—be rejected.
18. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 9 > Issue: 3
William Tuckwell, Kai Tanter Scorekeeping trolls
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Keith DeRose defends contextualism: the view that the truth-conditions of knowledge ascriptions vary with the context of the ascriber. Mark Richard has criticised contextualism for being unable to vindicate intuitions about disagreement. To account for these intuitions, DeRose has proposed truth-conditions for “knows” called the Gap view. According to this view, knowledge ascriptions are true iff the epistemic standards of each conversational participant are met, false iff each participant's standards aren't met, and truth-valueless otherwise. An implication of the Gap view is that people with divergent standards can enter conversations and thereby render knowledge claims gappy. We characterise this as a form of trolling. We argue that trolling results in unacceptably counterintuitive implications and that this constitutes a reductio against the Gap view. We also briefly explore the implications of trolling for other contextualist views about “knows,” as well as a broader class of context sensitive expressions.
19. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 9 > Issue: 2
Issue Information
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
editorial
20. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 9 > Issue: 2
Changes to the Board of Editors
view |  rights & permissions | cited by