Cover of Faith and Philosophy
Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Browse by:



Displaying: 1-12 of 12 documents


articles
1. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 27 > Issue: 4
C. Stephen Evans Wisdom as Conceptual Understanding: A Christian Platonist Perspective
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
This article argues that Platonism provides a plausible account of wisdom, one that is especially attractive for Christians. Christian Platonism sees wisdom as conceptual understanding; it is a “knowledge of the Forms.” To be convincing this view requires us to see understanding as including an appreciation of the relations between concepts as well as the value of the possible ways of being that concepts disclose. If the Forms are Divine Ideas, then we can see why God is both supremely wise and the source of all human wisdom. The account of wisdom provided helps explain the relation between wisdom and knowledge, the connection between wisdom and emotion, and much about how wisdom is acquired. The view also helps explain why someone who lacks extensive propositional knowledge can still be wise, and it helps us see why an understanding of the Biblical narrative and participation in the life of the Church can be important aids in the development of wisdom.
2. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 27 > Issue: 4
JT Paasch Arius and Athanasius on the Production of God’s Son
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Arius maintains that the Father must produce the Son without any pre-existing ingredients (ex nihilo) because no such ingredients are available to the Father. Athanasius denies this, insisting not only that the Father himself becomes an ingredient in the Son, but also that the Son inherits his divine properties from that ingredient. I argue, however, that it is difficult to explain exactly how the Son could inherit certain properties but not others from something he is not identical to, just as it is difficult to explain the precise way that a statue inherits certain properties but not others from the lump of bronze it is made from.
3. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 27 > Issue: 4
Kenneth Einar Himma The Problem of Unresolved Wrongdoing
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Many Christians believe that, because of divine grace, any person who repents of sin, accepts Christianity, and has genuinely authentic faith in God is forgiven for her sins and spared completely of the torments of hell. I argue that this idea is difficult to reconcile with certain Christian doctrines and common, though not universal, moral intuitions about wrongdoing and punishment. The main steps are as follows. The violation of an obligation creates a moral debt that requires correction by compensation, punishment, and/or forgiveness; a wrong that is never punished, compensated, or forgiven perpetuates a continuing injustice by leaving a debt unpaid. If it is true that one person’s forgiveness cannot release the wrongdoer of a moral debt owed to someone else, then God’s forgiveness cannot release a wrongdoer from the moral debts she owes to human victims of her wrongs. Something must be done, as a moral matter, to deal with those existing moral debts before a saved sinner can enjoy the eternal bliss promised to the faithful.
4. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 27 > Issue: 4
Travis Dumsday Divine Hiddenness, Free-Will, and the Victims of Wrongdoing
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Schellenberg’s hiddenness argument against the existence of God has generated a great deal of discussion. One prominent line of reply has been the idea that God refrains from making His existence more apparent in order to safeguard our moral freedom. Schellenberg has provided extensive counter-replies to this idea. My goal here is to pursue an alternate line of response, though one that still makes some reference to the importance of free-will. It will be argued that God may remain temporarily ‘hidden’ to some people not merely in order to allow their free moral choice, but because His proper allowance of such choice has led to a great deal of suffering on the part of the victims of wicked choices. If His existence were constantly obvious to those victims, even in the midst of their victimization, many of them would be led to an attitude of enmity, even hatred, toward God.
5. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 27 > Issue: 4
Wes Morriston Beginningless Past, Endless Future, and the Actual Infinite
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
One of the principal lines of argument deployed by the friends of the kalām cosmological argument against the possibility of a beginningless series of events is a quite general argument against the possibility of an actual infinite. The principal thesis of the present paper is that if this argument worked as advertised, parallel considerations would force us to conclude, not merely that a series of discrete, successive events must have a first member, but also that such a series must have a final member. Anyone who thinks that an endless series of events is possible must therefore reject this popular line of argument against the possibility of an actual infinite.
6. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 27 > Issue: 4
William Lane Craig Taking Tense Seriously in Differentiating Past and Future: A Response to Wes Morriston
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Wes Morriston argues that even if we take an endless series of events to be merely potentially, rather than actually, infinite, still no distinction between a beginningless and an endless series of events has been established which is relevant to arguments against the metaphysical possibility of an actually infinite number of things: if a beginningless series is impossible, so is an endless series. The success of Morriston’s argument, however, comes to depend on rejecting the characterization of an endless series of events as a potential infinite. It turns out that according to his own analysis it is vitally relevant whether the series of events is potentially, as opposed to actually, infinite. If it is reasonable to maintain that an endless series of events is potentially infinite while a beginningless series is actually infinite, then a relevant distinction has been established for any person who thinks that an actual infinite cannot exist.
7. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 27 > Issue: 4
William J. Wainwright In Defense of Non-Natural Theistic Realism: A Response to Wielenberg
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Eric Wielenberg and I agree that basic moral truths are necessarily true. But Wielenberg thinks that, because these truths are necessary, they require no explanation, and I do not: some basic moral truths are not self-explanatory. I argue that Wielenberg’s reasons for thinking that my justification of that claim is inadequate are ultimately unconvincing.
reviews
8. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 27 > Issue: 4
R.W. Fischer Theism and Ultimate Explanation: The Necessary Shape of Contingency
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
9. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 27 > Issue: 4
James Beilby Tayloring Reformed Epistemology: Charles Taylor, Alvin Plantinga and the de jure Challenge to Christian Belief
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
10. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 27 > Issue: 4
David Basinger God, Evil, and Design: An Introduction to the Philosophical Issues
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
11. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 27 > Issue: 4
Francis J. Beckwith Abortion: Three Perspectives
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
12. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 27 > Issue: 4
Edward Feser Real Essentialism
view |  rights & permissions | cited by