Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Browse by:



Displaying: 1-12 of 12 documents


articles
1. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 26 > Issue: 1
Stephen R. Palmquist KANT’S RELIGIOUS ARGUMENT FOR THE EXISTENCE OF GOD: THE ULTIMATE DEPENDENCE OF HUMAN DESTINY ON DIVINE ASSISTANCE
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
After reviewing Kant’s well-known criticisms of the traditional proofs of God’s existence and his preferred moral argument, this paper presents a detailedanalysis of a densely-packed theistic argument in Religion within the Bounds of Bare Reason. Humanity’s ultimate moral destiny can be fulfilled only through organized religion, for only by participating in a religious community (or “church”) can we overcome the evil in human nature. Yet we cannot conceive how such a community can even be founded without presupposing God’s existence. Viewing God as the internal moral lawgiver, empowering a community of believers, is Kant’s ultimate rationale for theistic belief.
2. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 26 > Issue: 1
Erik J. Wielenberg In Defense of Non-Natural, Non-Theistic Moral Realism
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Many believe that objective morality requires a theistic foundation. I maintain that there are sui generis objective ethical facts that do not reduce to naturalor supernatural facts. On my view, objective morality does not require an external foundation of any kind. After explaining my view, I defend it against a variety of objections posed by William Wainwright, William Lane Craig, and J. P. Moreland.
3. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 26 > Issue: 1
Jack Mulder, Jr. KIERKEGAARD AND NATURAL REASON: A CATHOLIC ENCOUNTER
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In this paper I consider Kierkegaard’s pseudonymous attack on natural theology with respect to how it lines up with Catholic thought on that topic. I argue that Kierkegaard’s recently shown similarities to accounts of basic beliefs raise an interesting question when a Catholic hybrid of basic beliefs and natural theology, which I develop in the paper, is considered. Kierkegaard does not attack what we might call natural reason, or a natural awareness of God’s existence, only natural theology’s demonstrative capabilities, and his reasons for doing the latter, in our current epistemological climate, are shown to be mistaken.
4. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 26 > Issue: 1
Ian Wilks SKEPTICAL THEISM AND EMPIRICAL UNFALSIFIABILITY
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Arguments strong enough to justify skeptical theism will be strong enough to justify the position that every claim about God is empirically unfalsifiable. This fact is problematic because that position licenses further arguments which are clearly unreasonable, but which the skeptical theist cannot consistently accept as such. Avoiding this result while still achieving the theoretical objectives looked for in skeptical theism appears to demand an impossibly nuanced position.
5. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 26 > Issue: 1
Justin P. McBrayer CORNEA AND INDUCTIVE EVIDENCE
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
One of the primary tools in the theist’s defense against “noseeum” arguments from evil is an epistemic principle concerning the Conditions Of ReasoNableEpistemic Access (CORNEA) which places an important restriction on what counts as evidence. However, CORNEA is false because it places too strong acondition on what counts as inductive evidence. If CORNEA is true, we lack evidence for a great many of our inductive beliefs. This is because CORNEA amounts to a sensitivity constraint on evidence, and inductive evidence is often insensitive. So unless a theist is also an inductive skeptic, she must abandon CORNEA in responding to this sort of argument from evil.
6. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 26 > Issue: 1
Daniel M. Johnson THE SENSE OF DEITY AND BEGGING THE QUESTION WITH ONTOLOGICAL AND COSMOLOGICAL ARGUMENTS
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Calvin famously interprets Romans 1 as ascribing human knowledge of God in nature not to inferences from created things (natural theology) but to a “senseof deity” that all people share and sinfully suppress. I want to suggest that the sense of deity interpretation actually provides the resources for explaining thepersuasive power and usefulness of natural theology. Specifi cally, I will argue that understanding certain ontological and cosmological arguments as dependenton the sense of deity preserves their ability to persuade while helping solve serious problems with the justifi cation of their premises. In the case of the ontological argument, this will provide a new response to the most serious objection that the argument faces, the charge that it begs the question.
book reviews
7. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 26 > Issue: 1
Paul K. Moser Christ and Horrors: The Coherence of Christology
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
8. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 26 > Issue: 1
Robert C. Roberts Wisdom in Love: Kierkegaard and the Ancient Quest for Emotional Integrity
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
9. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 26 > Issue: 1
Dale Tuggy Paradox in Christian Theology: An Analysis of Its Presence, Character, and Epistemic Status
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
10. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 26 > Issue: 1
William Lad Sessions The God of Metaphysics: Being a Study of the Metaphysics and Religious Doctrines of Spinoza, Hegel, Kierkegaard, T. H. Green, Bernard Bosanquet, Josiah Royce, A. N. Whitehead, Charles Hartshorne, and Concluding with a Defence of Pantheistic Idealism
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
11. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 26 > Issue: 1
Nancy Frankenberry Religions, Reasons and Gods: Essays in Cross-Cultural Philosophy of Religion
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
12. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 26 > Issue: 1
Kurt Smith The Philosopher in Early Modern Europe
view |  rights & permissions | cited by