Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Browse by:



Displaying: 1-11 of 11 documents


articles
1. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 25 > Issue: 1
Jeffrey E. Brower Making Sense of Divine Simplicity
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
According to the doctrine of divine simplicity, God is an absolutely simple being lacking any distinct metaphysical parts, properties, or constituents. Although this doctrine was once an essential part of traditional philosophical theology, it is now widely rejected as incoherent. In this paper, I develop an interpretation of the doctrine designed to resolve contemporary concerns about its coherence, as well as to show precisely what is required to make sense of divine simplicity.
2. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 25 > Issue: 1
Katherin A. Rogers Evidence for God from Certainty
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Human beings can have “strongly certain” beliefs—indubitable, veridical beliefs with a unique phenomenology—about necessarily true propositions like 2+2=4. On the plausible assumption that mathematical entities are platonic abstracta, naturalist theories fail to provide an adequate causal explanation for such beliefs because they cannot show how the propositional content of the causally inert abstracta can figure in a chain of physical causes. Theories which explain such beliefs as “corresponding” to the abstracta, but without any causal relationship, entail impossibilities. God, or a very god-like being, provides the best causal explanation for such beliefs.
3. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 25 > Issue: 1
David Paulsen, Brett McDonald Joseph Smith and the Trinity: An Analysis and Defense of the Social Model of the Godhead
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
The theology of Joseph Smith remains controversial and at times divisive in the broader Christian community. This paper takes Smith’s trinitarian theologyas its point of departure and seeks to accomplish four interrelated goals: (1) to provide a general defense of “social trinitarianism” from some of the major objections raised against it; (2) to express what we take to be Smith’s understanding of the Trinity; (3) to analyze the state of modern ST and (4) to argue that, as a form of ST, Smith’s views contribute to the present discussion amongst proponents of ST.
4. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 25 > Issue: 1
Peter A. Graham Warfield on Divine Foreknowledge and Human Freedom
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Warfield (1997, 2000) argues that divine foreknowledge and human freedom are compatible. He assumes for conditional proof that there is a necessarilyexistent omniscient being. He also assumes that it is possible for there to be a person who both does something and could have avoided doing it. As supportfor this latter premise he points to the fact that nearly every participant to the debate accepts the falsity of logical fatalism. Appealing to this consensus, however, renders the argument question-begging, for that consensus has emerged only against the backdrop of an assumption that there is no necessarily existent omniscient being.
5. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 25 > Issue: 1
Jeremy Gwiazda Remarks on Jove and Thor
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In “How an Unsurpassable Being can Create a Surpassable World,” Daniel and Frances Howard-Snyder employ a fascinating thought experiment in anattempt to show that a morally unsurpassable being can create a surpassable world. Imagine that for each positive integer there is a world that a good,omnipotent, omniscient being can create. Jove randomly selects a number and creates the corresponding world; Thor simply creates world 888. The Howard-Snyders argue that it is logically possible that Jove is morally unsurpassable. William Rowe counters that Thor morally surpasses Jove, thus contradictingthe claim that Jove is morally unsurpassable. Does either Jove or Thor morally surpass the other? How do their strategies compare? Could a morally unsurpassable being employ Jove’s strategy? The purpose of this paper is to answer these questions.
6. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 25 > Issue: 1
Kevin Diller Are Sin and Evil Necessary for a Really Good World?: Questions for Alvin Plantinga's Felix Culpa Theodicy
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Arguably, the most philosophically nuanced defense of a Felix Culpa theodicy, born out of serious theological reflection, is to be found in Alvin Plantinga’srecent article entitled “Superlapsarianism, or ‘O Felix Culpa.’” In this paper I look at Plantinga’s argument for the necessity of evil as a means to God’s fargreater ends and raise four objections to it. The arguments I give are aimed at the theological adequacy of explaining the emergence of evil as a functionalgood. I conclude that Plantinga’s Felix Culpa approach fails to demonstrate the necessity of evil for heightened intimacy with God, and collides with agent-centeredconsiderations. Moreover, I argue that all Felix Culpa theodicies reverse the apparent value God places on means and ends in the economy of salvation, while lending to evil a potentially morally and theologically distorting rational legitimacy.
reviews
7. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 25 > Issue: 1
Paul C. Anders In Defense of Natural Theology: A Post-Humean Assessment
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
8. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 25 > Issue: 1
David Bradshaw Faith, Reason and the Existence of God
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
9. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 25 > Issue: 1
Robert Aaron Johnson The Most Real Being: A Biblical and Philosophical Defense of Divine Determinism
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
10. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 25 > Issue: 1
Joshua C. Thurow Christian Philosophical Theology
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
11. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 25 > Issue: 1
Noel Hendrickson Crucible of Reason: Intentional Action, Practical Rationality, and Weakness of Will
view |  rights & permissions | cited by