Cover of Environmental Ethics
Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Browse by:



Displaying: 21-40 of 53 documents


discussion papers
21. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 35 > Issue: 3
Elspeth Whitney The Lynn White Thesis: Reception and Legacy
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
If we are to accurately gauge the validity of Lynn White, Jr.’s thesis as articulated in his article, “The Historical Roots of Our Ecologic Crisis” (1967), we must bring together recent research not only in the fields of environmental ethics and ecotheology but also in environmental history. We must also consider White’s work as a whole, including his Medieval Technology and Social Change (1962), which has been ignored for the most part by non-medievalists. Environmental history provides a corrective to White by anchoring medieval attitudes and practices in specific times and places and demonstrating that the medieval period was not monolithic or uniform with respect to attitudes toward nature. Recent work by medieval environmental historians confirms that while many of the broad claims made by White in “Roots” and Medieval Technology and Social Change must be strongly qualified, his central point that medieval agriculture was an important part of European environmental history has been largely sustained.
22. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 35 > Issue: 3
Jeff Baldwin What Ought I to Eat?: Toward an Ethical Biospheric Political Economy
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Humanity’s food production activities profoundly affect our planet’s biosphere. While people commonly apply various ethical frameworks in making food choices, few consider the individual’s relationship with or obligation to our biosphere, the source of all food. A practical ethical framework capable of evaluating the relative biospheric goodness of various food production systems is needed. Toward that end there are three foundational concepts: (1) an elaboration of Marx’s concept of value here extended to incorporate the life activity of all living beings, (2) a refocusing of ecological thought to include the value and the spaces created by nonhuman communities, and (3) a characterization of power which also works to include all life and to obviate certain human/biospheric dichotomies. This approach joins the Marxist theory of value and exchange—which has well developed ethical principles—with ecology, which offers key insights into biotic relationships, but as a science eschews ethical positions. It is important to attend not only to the value resident in nonhuman bodies, but also to the value that these co-inhabitants invest in biospheric spaces—a matter often overlooked in both the social and natural sciences.
23. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 35 > Issue: 3
Ryan Gunderson Animal Epistemology and Ethics in Schopenhauerian Metaphysics
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Within Arthur Schopenhauer’s pessimistic philosophy he set aside a special place for animals. Not only did Schopenhauer show great affection for other species and repeatedly criticize Western anthropocentrism, but he also argued that we could know a great deal about animals by intimately knowing ourselves. Although currently underdeveloped, Schopenhauer’s introspective methodology sheds light on how we can begin to mend the epistemic human-animal boundary through his emphasis on immediate, concrete knowledge and intuition. In practice too, Schopenhauer’s metaphysically grounded ethical system of compassion offers an alternative to both utilitarianism and deontology to bridge the human-animal moral boundary. For Schopenhauer, if a person recognizes the identical, underlying substance of their self and the animal kingdom, he or she will extend loving kindness and justice to all creatures.
book reviews
24. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 35 > Issue: 3
Roger J. H. King Anthony Karvonen. Politics of Urban Runoff: Nature, Technology, and the Sustainable City
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
25. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 35 > Issue: 3
Robert L. Chapman William R. Jordon III and George M. Lubick. Making Nature Whole: A History of Ecological Restoration
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
26. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 35 > Issue: 3
Piers H. G. Stephens Ben A. Minteer. Refounding Environmental Ethics: Pragmatism, Principle, and Practice
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
27. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 35 > Issue: 3
Andrew Biro Deborah Cook. Adorno on Nature
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
28. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 35 > Issue: 3
Ilan Safit Simon P. James. The Presence of Nature: A Study in Phenomenology and Environmental Philosophy
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
29. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 35 > Issue: 3
Nancy M. Rourke Donna Bowman and Clayton Crockett, eds. Cosmology, Ecology, and the Energy of God
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
comment
30. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 35 > Issue: 3
David Dillard-Wright In Defense of the Ark of the Possible: A Reply to Chris Nagle
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
31. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 35 > Issue: 2
News and Notes
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
32. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 35 > Issue: 2
Johanna Seibt From The Guest Editor: Climate Change, Sustainability, and Environmental Ethics
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
features
33. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 35 > Issue: 2
Annick Hedlund-de Witt Worldviews and Their Significance for the Global Sustainable Development Debate
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Insight into worldviews is essential for approaches aiming to design and support (more) sustainable pathways for society, both locally and globally. However, the nature of worldviews remains controversial, and it is still unclear how the concept can best be operationalized in the context of research and practice. One way may be by developing a framework for the understanding and operationalization worldviews by investigating various conceptualizations of the term in the history of philosophy. Worldviews can be understood as inescapable, overarching systems of meaning and meaning making that to a substantial extent inform how humans interpret, enact, and co-create reality. Moreover, worldviews are profoundly historically and developmentally situated. An Integrative Worldview Framework (IWF) can operationalize worldviews by differentiating five interrelated aspects: ontology, epistemology, axiology, anthropology, and societal vision. The evolution of the worldview concept is suggestive of an increasing reflexivity, creativity, responsibility, and inclusiveness—each of which are qualities that appear to be crucial for the global sustainable development debate.
34. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 35 > Issue: 2
Franziska Martinsen, Johanna Seibt Climate Change and the Concept of Shared Ecological Responsibility
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
The recent debate about justice and responsibility increasingly tries to accommodate a new type of agentive situation in which local short-term actions have global long-term consequences due to the action’s embedding in complex interactional networks. Currently the debate is shifting focus from the spatial to the temporal dimension of such wide-scope results of individual actions. This shift from “global ethics” to “intergenerational ethics” and, in particular, “climate ethics” requires some new analytical concepts, however. A definition of wide-scope responsibility aimed at articulating our moral concerns about emergent effects in complex systems, such as climate change, is needed. Working from Iris Marion Young’s “social connection model of responsibility,” a notion of shared ecological responsibility with global and intergenerational scope can be developed. This account is not affected by the so-called non-identity objection to intergenerational ethics. From an action-theoretic rather than normative perspective, the account is “ethically parametrized” in the sense that it can be combined with different conceptions of structural and intergenerational justice. The account can be used to support a concrete climate policy proposal: the “Greenhouse Development Rights Framework.”
35. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 35 > Issue: 2
Derek Bell How Should We Think about Climate Justice?
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Climate change raises questions of justice. Some people are enjoying the benefits of energy use and other emissions-generating activities, but those activities are causing other people to suffer the burdens of climate change. Political philosophers have begun to pay more attention to the problem of “climate justice.” However, contributors to the literature have made quite different methodological assumptions about how we should develop a theory of climate justice and defend principles of climate justice. So far, there has been little systematic or detailed discussion of these methodological issues. One way to approach these issues is by developing a methodological framework for thinking about climate justice, or more specifically, a five-stage framework, drawing on recent work on two issues: first, the distinction between “ideal” and “non-ideal” theory; and second, the distinction between “integrationist” and “isolationist” approaches to environmental and climate justice. This methodological framework can also be used to inform critical analysis of extant theories of climate justice, for example, through a critical discussion of two key features of the theory of climate justice developed by Simon Caney.
discussion papers
36. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 35 > Issue: 2
Kristian Høyer Toft The Human Rights Approach to Climate Change: An Overview
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
It is often argued that concerns about the equity of a global climate agreement might appropriately be addressed in the language of human rights. The human rights approach has been promoted by a number of international political actors, including the UN Human Rights Council. As such, human rights are instrumentally applied as a solution to what could be called the “justice problem” in climate negotiations. In order to assess the degree to which human rights could be a useful approach to the justice problem with regard to to climate change, four major issues need to be examined. First, there is the distinction between human rights as protection against climate change versus the right to emit greenhouse gases. Both understandings are found in the debate on climate justice, but they are often not made explicit. Second, the “human rights as protection” approach with a focus on (a) right holders, both presently and in the future, needs to be elucidated, as well as (b) the human rights principles that are at stake, and (c) the duties and duty holders involved. Third, the human right to emit greenhouse gases needs to be clarified in the context of subsistence rights and equal per capita emission rights. Finally, there is the question of whether the cosmopolitan conception of human rights is at odds with the goal of ensuring that individuals assume responsibility for their own carbon-dependent lifestyle.
37. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 35 > Issue: 2
Robert Huseby John Rawls and Climate Justice: An Amendment to The Law of Peoples
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
To what extent does John Rawls’ theory of international justice meet the normative challenges posed by climate change? There are two broadly compatible Rawlsian ways of addressing climate change. The first alternative is based on the two principles that Rawls applies to the domains of international and intergenerational justice (the Principle of Assistance, and the Principle of Just Savings). The second alternative starts from Rawls’ general theory of international justice, in particular his idea of a Society of Peoples, which is an idealized vision of a peaceful and stable association of peoples that are internally well-ordered, and share a desire to respect and uphold international law. Given (a) the statutes peoples are willing to observe, (b) the defining characteristics of peoples, and (c) the fact that Rawls indicates that his own rendering of international law is incomplete, there may be grounds for proposing an additional statute, or an amendment, to The Law of Peoples, that pertains to climate change and that does not contradict, but rather follows from, the general framework of the theory. The latter alternative provides a more viable account of climate justice than critics has hitherto acknowledged.
book reviews
38. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 35 > Issue: 2
Jerome A. Stone Whitney A. Bauman, Richard R. Bohannon II, and Kevin J. O’Brien, eds. Inherited Land: The Changing Grounds of Religion and Ecology
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
39. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 35 > Issue: 2
Mick Smith Andrew Biro, ed.: Critical Ecologies: The Frankfurt School and Contemporary Environmental Crisis
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
40. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 35 > Issue: 2
Clark Wolf Paul Thompson. The Agrarian Vision: Sustainability and Environmental Ethics
view |  rights & permissions | cited by