Cover of Faith and Philosophy
Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Browse by:



Displaying: 21-40 of 43 documents


book reviews
21. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 36 > Issue: 3
Michael Thune God, Science, and Religious Diversity: A Defense of Theism, by Robert T. Lehe
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
22. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 36 > Issue: 3
Benjamin B. DeVan The Devil’s Redemption: A New History and Interpretation of Christian Universalism, Volumes 1 and 2, by Michael J. McClymond
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
articles
23. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 36 > Issue: 2
Jc Beall, Jared Henderson A Neglected Qua Solution to the Fundamental Problem of Christology
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
We advance a neglected QUA solution to the fundamental problem of Christology. Our chief aim is to put the view on the theological table, leaving future debate to tell its ultimate fate. After presenting the view we measure it against standard problems that confront extant QUA views and also against objections peculiar to the proposed view.
24. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 36 > Issue: 2
Joseph Jedwab, John A. Keller Paraphrase and the Doctrine of the Trinity
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
The Doctrine of the Trinity says that there is one God, that there are three divine Persons, and that each divine Person is God. The Logical Problem of the Trinity is that these claims seem logically inconsistent. We argue that any coherent and orthodox solution to the Logical Problem must use the technique of paraphrase: a logically or metaphysically more perspicuous reformulation. If so, discussions of paraphrase deserve more prominence in the literature on the Doctrine of the Trinity. We also show that such explicit discussion has important implications for theorizing about the Trinity.
25. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 36 > Issue: 2
Robert C. Roberts Joys: A Brief Moral and Christian Geography
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
This paper is an initial effort preparatory for a more thorough “theology of joys.” I distinguish joys from other kinds of pleasure and argue that joy can be seen as the form of all the so-called positive emotions (the ones that feel good). So joy is properly treated in the plural: joys come in a variety of kinds. I distinguish canonical (joys with single-term names) from non-canonical joys. The worthiness of joys is primarily a function of their objects—what the joys are about. I look at a few examples of joys that appear in the New Testament and sketch the relation of joys to happiness.
26. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 36 > Issue: 2
Jeroen de Ridder Against Quasi-Fideism
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Duncan Pritchard has recently ventured to carve out a novel position in the epistemology of religious belief called quasi-fideism. Its core is an application of ideas from Wittgensteinian hinge epistemology to religious belief. Among its many advertised benefits are that it can do justice to two seemingly conflicting ideas about religious belief, to wit: (a) that it is, at least at some level, a matter of ungrounded faith, but also (b) that it can be epistemically rationally grounded. In this paper, I argue that quasi-fideism fails. Its central tenets either have unattractive consequences or are implausible.
27. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 36 > Issue: 2
Jonathan Curtis Rutledge Perspectival Skeptical Theism
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Skeptical theists have paid insufficient attention to non-evidential components of epistemic rationality. I address this lacuna by constructing an alternative perspectivalist understanding of epistemic rationality and defeat that, when applied to skeptical theism, yields a more demanding standard for reasonably affirming the crucial premise of the evidential argument from suffering. The resulting perspectival skeptical theism entails that someone can be justified in believing that gratuitous suffering exists only if they are not subject to closure-of-inquiry defeat; that is, a type of defeat that prevents reasonable belief that p even if p is very probable on an agent’s evidence.
reviews
28. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 36 > Issue: 2
Craig Warmke Idealism: New Essays in Metaphysics, edited by Tyron Goldschmidt and Kenneth L. Pearce
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
29. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 36 > Issue: 2
Matthew A. Benton A Grotesque in the Garden, by Hud Hudson
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
30. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 36 > Issue: 2
Andrew M. Bailey Maximal God: A New Defence of Perfect Being Theism, by Yujin Nagasawa
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
31. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 36 > Issue: 2
Michelle Panchuk The Hiddenness of God, by Michael C. Rea
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
32. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 36 > Issue: 2
Jordan Wessling The Christian Idea of God: A Philosophical Foundation for Faith, by Keith Ward
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
33. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 36 > Issue: 1
Mark C. Murphy From the Editor
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
article
34. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 36 > Issue: 1
Rebecca Chan Transformed By Faith
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Appealing to self-interest is a common way of justifying the rationality of religious faith. For instance, Pascal’s wager relies upon the expected value of choosing the life of faith being infinite. Similarly, many contemporary arguments for the rationality of faith turn on whether it is better for an agent to have faith rather than lack it. In this paper, I argue, contra Pascal, that considerations of self-interest do not make choosing faith rational because they fail to take into account the way the self is transformed by faith.
35. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 36 > Issue: 1
Joshua Cockayne Common Ritual Knowledge
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
How can participating in a liturgy allow us to know God? Recent pathbreaking work on the epistemology of liturgy has argued that liturgy allows individuals to gain ritual knowledge of God by coming to know-how to engage God. However, since liturgy (as it is ordinarily practiced) is a group act, I argue that we need to give an account to explain how a group can know God by engaging with liturgy. If group know-how is reducible to instances of individual know-how, then the existing accounts are sufficient for explaining a group’s knowing-how to engage God. However, I argue, there are good reasons to suppose that reductive accounts of group know-how fail. In this paper, I propose a non-reductive account of common ritual knowledge, according to which the group knows-how to engage God in liturgy.
36. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 36 > Issue: 1
Tyler Paytas Of Providence and Puppet Shows: Divine Hiddenness as Kantian Theodicy
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Although the free-will reply to divine hiddenness is often associated with Kant, the argument typically presented in the literature is not the strongest Kantian response. Kant’s central claim is not that knowledge of God would preclude the possibility of transgression, but rather that it would preclude one’s viewing adherence to the moral law as a genuine sacrifice of self-interest. After explaining why the Kantian reply to hiddenness is superior to standard formulations, I argue that, despite Kant’s general skepticism about theodicy, his insights pertaining to hiddenness also provide the foundation for a new theodicy that merits serious attention.
37. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 36 > Issue: 1
Adam C. Pelser Temptation, Virtue, and the Character of Christ
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
The author of Hebrews writes that Jesus Christ was “tempted as we are, yet without sin” (Hebrews 4:15). Many Christians take the sinlessness of Jesus to imply that he was perfectly virtuous. Yet, susceptibility to the experience of at least some temptations, plausibly including those Jesus experienced, seems incompatible with the possession of perfect virtue. In an attempt to resolve this tension, I argue here that there are good reasons for believing that Jesus, while perfectly sinless, was not fully virtuous at the time of his temptations, but that he grew in virtue through overcoming temptation. If this is right, then Jesus Christ is an exemplar of character formation who is able to “sympathize with our weaknesses” in an important way that Christians have largely overlooked.
38. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 36 > Issue: 1
Kegan J. Shaw A Plea for the Theist in the Street: A Defense of Liberalism in the Epistemology of Religious Experience
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
It can be easy to assume that since the “theist in the street” is unaware of any of the traditional arguments for theism, he or she is not in position to offer independent rational support for believing that God exists. I argue that that is false if we accept with William Alston that “manifestation beliefs” can enjoy rational support on the basis of suitable religious experiences. I make my case by defending the viability of a Moorean-style proof for theism—a proof for the existence of God that parallels in structure G. E. Moore’s famous proof for the existence of the external world. I argue that this shows that even if the theist in the street has nothing to offer for helping to convince the religious sceptic, this needn’t entail that she cannot offer independent rational support in defense of her theistic belief.
reviews
39. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 36 > Issue: 1
Andrew Moon Knowledge, Belief, and God: New Insights in Religious Epistemology, edited by Matthew A. Benton, John Hawthorne, and Dani Rabinowitz
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
40. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 36 > Issue: 1
Adam Green New Models of Religious Understanding, edited by Fiona Ellis
view |  rights & permissions | cited by