Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Browse by:



Displaying: 21-40 of 50 documents


reviews
21. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 25 > Issue: 3
Thomas L. Carson Lying: An Augustinian Theology of Duplicity
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
22. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 25 > Issue: 3
Michael A. Cantrell Christianity and the Soul of the University: Faith as a Foundation for Intellectual Community
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
23. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 25 > Issue: 3
Paul C. Anders Is Nature Enough?: Meaning and Truth in the Age of Science
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
24. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 25 > Issue: 3
Agnaldo Cuoco Portugal Atheism: Very Short Introduction
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
25. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 25 > Issue: 3
David Vander Laan Rethinking Human Nature: A Christian Materialist Alternative to the Soul
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
26. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 25 > Issue: 3
William Hasker Providence, Evil and the Openness of God
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
articles
27. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 25 > Issue: 2
Marilyn McCord Adams PLANTINGA ON “FELIX CULPA”: ANALYSIS AND CRITIQUE
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In “Supralapsarianism, or ‘O Felix Culpa,’” Alvin Plantinga turns from defensive apologetics to the project of Christian explanation and offers a supralapsarian theodicy: the reason God made us in a world like this is that God wanted to create a world including the towering goods of Incarnation and atonement—goods which are appropriate only in worlds containing a sufficient amount of sin, suffering, and evil as well. Plantinga’s approach makes human agents and their sin, suffering and evil, instrumental means to the end of God’s cosmic aims. I press the objection that means/end conceptuality is inadequate to explain how God is loving and merciful (as opposed to abusive) towards human sinners and sufferers. Plantinga’s theodicy remains under-developed without an explanation of how Incarnation and atonement benefit them.
28. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 25 > Issue: 2
Hugh Rice FAITH AND MERIT
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Can belief in God can be meritorious if not epistemically rational in the ordinary way? I argue that the primary condition to be met if a belief is to be meritoriousis that it is based on a good reason, and that to believe that something is so on the grounds that it would be good if it were can be to believe for a good reason.In particular I argue that to believe in God on the grounds that it would be good if He existed can be to believe for a good reason, and that such a belief can,therefore, be meritorious.
29. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 25 > Issue: 2
Robert Larmer C. S. LEWIS’S CRITIQUE OF HUME’S “ON MIRACLES”
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In this article I argue that C. S. Lewis is both a perceptive reader and trenchant critic of David Hume’s views on miracle.
30. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 25 > Issue: 2
Trent Dougherty EPISTEMOLOGICAL CONSIDERATIONS CONCERNING SKEPTICAL THEISM
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
The thesis of this short paper is that skeptical theism does not look very plausible from the perspective of a common sense epistemology. A corollary of this isthat anyone who finds common sense epistemology plausible and is attracted to skeptical theism has some work to do to show that they can form a plausiblewhole. The dialectical situation is that to the degree that this argument is a strong one, to that same degree (at least) the theorist who would like to combinecommon sense epistemology with skeptical theism has some work to do.
symposium on freedom and creation
31. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 25 > Issue: 2
David B. Burrell CREATOR/CREATURES RELATION: “THE DISTINCTION” VS.“ONTO-THEOLOGY”
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Can philosophical inquiry into divinity be authentic to its subject, God, without adapting its categories to the challenges of its scriptural inspiration, be that biblical or Quranic? This essay argues that it cannot, and that the adaptation, while it can be articulated in semantic terms, must rather amount to a transformation of standard philosophical strategies. Indeed, without such a radical transformation, “philosophy of religion” will inevitably mislead us into speaking of a “god” rather than our intended object.
articles
32. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 25 > Issue: 2
Richard Cross IDOLATRY AND RELIGIOUS LANGUAGE
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Upholding a univocity theory of religious language does not entail idolatry, because nothing about univocity entails misidentifying God altogether—which is what idolatry amounts to. Upholders and opponents of univocity can agree on the object to which they are ascribing various attributes, even if they do not agree on the attributes themselves. Neither does the defender of univocity have to maintain that there is anything real really shared by God and creatures. Furthermore, even if much of language is analogous, syllogistic argument—and hence theology’s scientific status, as accepted by the scholastics—requires univocity.
33. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 25 > Issue: 2
William Hasker ON BEHALF OF THE PAGANS AND THE IDOLATERS: A RESPONSE TO BURRELL
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In this comment I express my puzzlement about Burrell’s employment of “the distinction,” and request further clarification. I also discuss at some length his views concerning free will. I explain the libertarian view as I understand it and point out why his criticisms of it do not succeed. I sketch out his own view of created freedom, and raise certain questions concerning that view.
34. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 25 > Issue: 2
David B. Burrell RESPONSE TO CROSS AND HASKER
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
It is not often that one is graced with a mini-symposium upon reception of an article for publication, and for this I am grateful to Bill Hasker, who had to wait until after his editorship to respond to my provocative piece, and equally grateful to Richard Cross, whom Bill solicited for an assist. Since my piece called for a “radical transformation of standard philosophical strategies,” and Bill addressed that perspectival issue from the outset, while Richard focused on some axial semantic and epistemological contentions, I shall begin with Bill Hasker’s overall puzzlements, proceed to address some issues on which Richard Cross and I seem fated to disagree, and close by addressing the neuralgic point of created freedom, which both Hasker and I find axial to attempting to articulate the creator/creature relation. What gratifies me is the opportunity to interact with such sterling critics, and to try to ascertain whether we can advance a discussion (as Bill Hasker suggests) of issues which no sane human inquirer can ever pretend to “get right.”
book reviews
35. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 25 > Issue: 2
Sam Addison The Logical Foundations of Bradley’s Metaphysics: Judgment, Inference, and Truth
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
36. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 25 > Issue: 2
James E. Taylor Evidence and Faith: Philosophy and Religion Since the Seventeenth Century
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
37. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 25 > Issue: 2
Stewart Goetz My Way: Essays on Moral Responsibility
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
38. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 25 > Issue: 2
Frank B. Dilley Personal Identity in Theological Perspective
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
39. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 25 > Issue: 2
Paul Macdonald Reason and the Reasons of Faith
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
articles
40. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 25 > Issue: 1
Jeffrey E. Brower Making Sense of Divine Simplicity
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
According to the doctrine of divine simplicity, God is an absolutely simple being lacking any distinct metaphysical parts, properties, or constituents. Although this doctrine was once an essential part of traditional philosophical theology, it is now widely rejected as incoherent. In this paper, I develop an interpretation of the doctrine designed to resolve contemporary concerns about its coherence, as well as to show precisely what is required to make sense of divine simplicity.