>> Go to Current Issue

Faith and Philosophy

Volume 4, Issue 3, July 1987
Christianity and Ethical Theory (continued)

Table of Contents

Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Browse by:



Displaying: 1-13 of 13 documents


articles
1. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 4 > Issue: 3
James G. Hanink, Gary R. Mar What Euthyphro Couldn’t Have Said
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In this paper we argue for a simple version of Divine Command Morality, namely that an act’s being morally right consists in its being in accord with God’s will, and an act’s being morally wrong consists in its being contrary to God’s will. In so arguing, we contend that this simple version of Divine Command Morality is not subject to the Euthyphro dilemma, either as Plato or as contemporary critics have ordinarily proposed it. Nor, we maintain, is our position incompatible with the most adequate formulation of natural law ethics. Finally we explain why Euthyphro could not have made a better case for his own position.
2. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 4 > Issue: 3
Robert Merrihew Adams Divine Commands and the Social Nature of Obligation
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Divine command metaethics is one of those theories according to which the nature of obligation is grounded in personal or social relationships. In this paper I first try to show how facts about human relationships can fill some of the role that facts of obligation aresupposed to play, specifically with regard to moral motivation and guilt. Then I note certain problems that arise for social theories of obligation, and argue that they can be dealt with more adequately by an expansion of our vision of the social dimension of ethics to include God as the most important participant in our system of personal relationships.
3. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 4 > Issue: 3
Jeffrie G. Murphy Kantian Autonomy and Divine Commands
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
James Rachels has argued that a morally autonomous person (in Kant’s sense) could not consistently accept the authority of divine commands. Against Rachels, this essay argues (a) that the Kantian concept of moral autonomy is to be analyzed in terms of an agent’sresponsiveness to the best available moral reasons and (b) that it is simply question-begging against divine command theory to assume that such commands could not count as the best moral reasons available to an agent.
4. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 4 > Issue: 3
Gregory Mellema What is Optional in the Fulfillment of Duty?
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Moral duties are often described in terms of rigid requirements to perform, or refrain from performing, actions of certain specific types. In various theological traditions this point is often expressed in terms of the demands God places upon His creatures. However, there are several important ways, as Kant, Mill, and others have noted, in which the fulfillment of duty admits of options. In this paper an effort is made to offer a precise characterization of these ways. On this basis it is concluded that many duties are not of the form in which duties are commonly characterized.
5. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 4 > Issue: 3
Linda Zagzebski Does Ethics Need God?
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
This essay presents a moral argument for the rationality of theistic belief. If all I have to go on morally are my own moral intuitions and reasoning and those of others, I am rationally led to skepticism, both about the possibility of moral knowledge and about my moral effectiveness. This skepticism is extensive, amounting to moral despair. But such despair cannot be rational. It follows that the assumption of the argument must be false and I must be able to rely on more than my own human powers and those of others in attempting to live a moral life. The Christian God has such a function. Hence, if it is rational to attempt a moral life, it is rational to believe in the Christian God.
6. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 4 > Issue: 3
Patrick Goold Kierkegaard’s Christian Imperative
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
This paper describes a strategy for defending some of the core claims of Christianity from evidentialist critics. The strategy is neither epistemological nor based on considerations of ‘proper basicality’. Indeed, this strategy, if successful, shows Christian faith to be notmerely permissible but ethically obligatory. It does so by taking seriously the claim that faith is a virtue (in the classical sense) and that a reflecting conscience will discover this. The paper also hopes to contribute to Kierkegaard scholarship by offering a new interpretation both of Sickness Unto Death and, by implication, of Kierkegaard’s general significance for philosophy of religion.
7. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 4 > Issue: 3
Richard L. Purthill Alpha and Beta Virtues and Vices
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In this paper I argue that there are pairs of virtues relating to the same areas of human life, each with its characteristic excess and defect. The excess of one member of the pair is usually related to the defect of the other, and the defect of one to the excess of the other. One of these paired virtues is typically seen by our society as “masculine” the other as “feminine.” This leads to an undervaluing of one member of each pair and an over-valuing of the other.
discussion
8. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 4 > Issue: 3
David Basinger Middle Knowledge and Human Freedom: Some Clarifications
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
The concept of middle knowledge---God’s knowledge of what would in fact happen in every conceivable situation---is just beginning to receive the attention it deserves, For example, it is just now becoming clear to many that classical theism requires the affirmation of middle knowledge. But this concept is also coming under increasing criticism. The most significant of these, I believe, has been developed in a recent discussion by William Hasker, in which he argues that the concept of a true counterfactual of freedom is incoherent. I also believe, however, that his critique ultimately fails and specify why in the essay which follows.
9. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 4 > Issue: 3
William Hasker The Hardness of the Past: A Reply to Reichenbach
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
book reviews
10. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 4 > Issue: 3
David B. Burrell Spirit, Saints and Immortality
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
11. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 4 > Issue: 3
Arthur F. McGovern A Matter of Hope: A Theologian’s Reflections on the Thought of Karl Marx
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
12. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 4 > Issue: 3
Frederick D. Wilhelmsen An Interpretation of Existence
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
13. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 4 > Issue: 3
Robert F. Brown Introduction to Hegel’s Philosophy of Religion
view |  rights & permissions | cited by