Cover of Logos & Episteme
Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Displaying: 161-180 of 611 documents


research articles
161. Logos & Episteme: Volume > 11 > Issue: 1
Kok Yong Lee Stakes-Shifting Cases Reconsidered—What Shifts?: Epistemic Standards or Position?
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
It is widely accepted that our initial intuitions regarding knowledge attributions in stakes-shifting cases (e.g., Cohen’s Airport) are best explained by standards variantism, the view that the standards for knowledge may vary with contexts in an epistemically interesting way. Against standards variantism, I argue that no prominent account of the standards for knowledge can explain our intuitions regarding stakes-shifting cases. I argue that the only way to preserve our initial intuitions regarding such cases is to endorse position variantism, the view that one’s epistemic position may vary with contexts in an epistemically interesting way. Some had argued that epistemic position is incompatible with intellectualism. In reply, I point out that position variantism and intellectualism are compatible, if one’s truth-relevant factors with respect to p can vary with contexts in an epistemically interesting way.
162. Logos & Episteme: Volume > 11 > Issue: 1
Timothy Perrine On Some Arguments for Epistemic Value Pluralism
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Epistemic Value Monism is the view that there is only one kind of thing of basic, final epistemic value. Perhaps the most plausible version of Epistemic Value Monism is Truth Value Monism, the view that only true beliefs are of basic, final epistemic value. Several authors—notably Jonathan Kvanvig and Michael DePaul—have criticized Truth Value Monism by appealing to the epistemic value of things other than knowledge. Such arguments, if successful, would establish Epistemic Value Pluralism is true and Epistemic Value Monism is false. This paper critically examines those arguments, finding them wanting. However, I develop an argument for Epistemic Value Pluralism that succeeds which turns on general reflection on the nature of value.
163. Logos & Episteme: Volume > 11 > Issue: 1
Gregory Stoutenburg Luck, Knowledge, and Epistemic Probability
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Epistemic probability theories of luck come in two versions. They are easiest to distinguish by the epistemic property they claim eliminates luck. One view says that the property is knowledge. The other view says that the property is being guaranteed by a subject’s evidence. Asbjørn Steglich-Petersen defends the Knowledge Account (KA). He has recently argued that his view is preferable to my Epistemic Analysis of Luck (EAL), which defines luck in terms of evidential probability. In this paper, I defend EAL against Steglich-Petersen’s arguments, clarify the view, and argue for the explanatory significance of EAL with respect to some core epistemological issues. My overall goal is to show that an epistemic probability account of luck rooted in the concepts of evidence and evidential support remains a viable and fruitful overall account of luck.
discussion notes/debate
164. Logos & Episteme: Volume > 11 > Issue: 1
James Simpson Gettier Beliefs and Serious Beliefs: A Reply to Biro and Forrai
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In a recent exchange in the pages of this journal, John Biro responds to Gabor Forrai’s argument against Biro’s argument that in most, if not all, Gettier cases the belief condition, contra popular opinion, isn’t satisfied. In this note, I’ll argue that Biro’s response to Forrai satisfactorily resolves the first of Forrai’s two central objections to Biro’s argument that the belief condition isn’t satisfied in most, if not all, Gettier cases. But Biro’s response leaves mostly unaddressed the most plausible way of construing Forrai’s second objection. I’ll take up the mantle of successfully defending Biro’s argument from this more plausible construal of Forrai’s second objection. However, even though I’ll argue that Biro’s argument is in good shape with respect to Forrai’s objections, I’ll show that the definition of serious belief that Biro offers us is mistaken.
165. Logos & Episteme: Volume > 11 > Issue: 1
Notes on the Contributors
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
166. Logos & Episteme: Volume > 11 > Issue: 1
Logos and Episteme. Aims and Scope
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
167. Logos & Episteme: Volume > 11 > Issue: 1
Notes to Contributors
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
research articles
168. Logos & Episteme: Volume > 10 > Issue: 4
Scott Aikin, Brian Ribeiro Skeptical Theism and the Creep Problem
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Skeptical theism is the view that human knowledge and understanding are severely limited, compared to that of the divine. The view is deployed as an undercutting defeater for evidential arguments from evil. However, skeptical theism has broader skeptical consequences than those for the argument from evil. The epistemic principles of this skeptical creep are identified and shown to be on the road to global skepticism.
169. Logos & Episteme: Volume > 10 > Issue: 4
Tommaso Ostillio, Michal Bukat The Knobe Effect with Probable Outcomes and Availability Heuristic Triggers
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
This paper contributes to the existing philosophical literature on the Knobe Effect (KE) in two main ways: first, this paper disconfirms the KE by showing that the latter does not hold in contexts with probable outcomes; second, this paper shows that KE is strongly sensitive to the availability heuristic bias. In particular, this paper presents two main findings from three empirical tests carried out between 2016 and 2018: the first finding concerns the fact that if the issuer of a decision with consequences on third parties is unlikely to be perceived as unfriendly, then KE is reduced or absent; the second finding regards instead the fact that if an action has two possible outcomes (one likely to obtain with strong intensity and one likely to obtain with less intensity), then KE does not obtain for decisions whose side-effects have limited consequences on third parties.
170. Logos & Episteme: Volume > 10 > Issue: 4
Seungbae Park Surrealism Is Not an Alternative to Scientific Realism
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Surrealism holds that observables behave as if T were true, whereas scientific realism holds that T is true. Surrealism and scientific realism give different explanations of why T is empirically adequate. According to surrealism, T is empirically adequate because observables behave as if it were true. According to scientific realism, T is empirically adequate because it is true. I argue that the surrealist explanation merely clarifies the concept of empirical adequacy, whereas the realist explanation makes an inductive inference about T. Therefore, the surrealist explanation is a conceptual one, whereas the realist explanation is an empirical one, and the former is not an alternative to the latter.
171. Logos & Episteme: Volume > 10 > Issue: 4
Hans Rott Unstable Knowledge, Unstable Belief
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
An idea going back to Plato’s Meno is that knowledge is stable. Recently, a seemingly stronger and more exciting thesis has been advanced, namely that rational belief is stable. I sketch two stability theories of knowledge and rational belief, and present an example intended to show that knowledge need not be stable and rational belief need not be stable either. The second claim does not follow from the first, even if we take knowledge to be a special kind of rational belief. ‘Stability’ is an ambiguous term that has an internally conditional structure.
172. Logos & Episteme: Volume > 10 > Issue: 4
Michael J. Shaffer The Availability Heuristic and Inference to the Best Explanation
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
This paper shows how the availability heuristic can be used to justify inference to the best explanation in such a way that van Fraassen's infamous "best of a bad lot" objection can be adroitly avoided. With this end in mind, a dynamic and contextual version of the erotetic model of explanation sufficient to ground this response is presented and defended.
173. Logos & Episteme: Volume > 10 > Issue: 4
Xintong Wei The Permissible Norm of Truth and “Ought Implies Can”
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Many philosophers hold that a norm of truth governs the propositional attitude of belief. According to one popular construal of normativity, normativity is prescriptive in nature. The prescriptive norm can be formulated either in terms of obligation or permission: one ought to or may believe that p just in case p is true. It has been argued that the obligation norm is jointly incompatible with the maxim ought implies can and the assumption that there exists some truth that we cannot believe. The problem of the incompatible triad has motivated some to adopt the permissible norm of truth. I argue that the permissible norm faces an analogous problem of the incompatible triad.
discussion notes/debate
174. Logos & Episteme: Volume > 10 > Issue: 4
Moti Mizrahi Factivity and Epistemic Certainty: A Reply to Sankey
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
This is a reply to Howard Sankey’s comment (“Factivity or Grounds? Comment on Mizrahi”) on my paper, “You Can’t Handle the Truth: Knowledge = Epistemic Certainty,” in which I present an argument from the factivity of knowledge for the conclusion that knowledge is epistemic certainty. While Sankey is right that factivity does not entail epistemic certainty, the factivity of knowledge does entail that knowledge is epistemic certainty.
175. Logos & Episteme: Volume > 10 > Issue: 4
Howard Sankey Why Must Justification Guarantee Truth?: Reply to Mizrahi
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
This reply provides further grounds to doubt Mizrahi’s argument for an infallibilist theory of knowledge. It is pointed out that the fact that knowledge requires both truth and justification does not entail that the level of justification required for knowledge be sufficient to guarantee truth. In addition, an argument presented by Mizrahi appears to equivocate with respect to the interpretation of the phrase “p cannot be false”.
176. Logos & Episteme: Volume > 10 > Issue: 4
James Simpson Knowledge Doesn’t Require Epistemic Certainty: A Reply to Mizrahi
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In a recent discussion note in this journal, Moti Mizrahi offers us the following argument for the conclusion that knowledge requires epistemic certainty:1) If S knows that p on the grounds that e, then p cannot be false given e.2) If p cannot be false given e, then e makes p epistemically certain.3) Therefore, if S knows that p on the grounds that e, then e makes p epistemically certain.I’ll argue that (2) of Mizrahi’s argument is false, and so, Mizrahi’s argument is unsound.
177. Logos & Episteme: Volume > 10 > Issue: 4
Notes on the Contributors
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
178. Logos & Episteme: Volume > 10 > Issue: 4
Logos and Episteme. Aims and Scope
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
179. Logos & Episteme: Volume > 10 > Issue: 4
Notes to Contributors
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
research articles
180. Logos & Episteme: Volume > 10 > Issue: 3
Víctor Fernández Castro Inner Speech and Metacognition: A Defense of the Commitment-Based Approach
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
A widespread view in philosophy claims that inner speech is closely tied to human metacognitive capacities. This so-called format view of inner speech considers that talking to oneself allows humans to gain access to their own mental states by forming metarepresentation states through the rehearsal of inner utterances (section 2). The aim of this paper is to present two problems to this view (section 3) and offer an alternative view to the connection between inner speech and metacognition (section 4). According to this alternative, inner speech (meta)cognitive functions derivate from the set of commitments we mobilize in our communicative exchanges. After presenting this commitment-based approach, I address two possible objections (section 5).