Cover of Philosophy and Theology
Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Browse by:



Displaying: 21-26 of 26 documents


21. Philosophy and Theology: Volume > 27 > Issue: 1
John-Mark L. Miravalle The Trinity's Choice: Oppy, Bergson, and God's Decision to Create
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
If God’s choice to create the universe is an unnecessary choice, then, Oppy argues, something contingent is ultimately at the origin of the universe, and as long as “brute contingency” is the basis for the universe’s existence, why bother with the additional postulate of a necessary being? Bergson’s work on free will, however, coupled with traditional trinitarian theology, suggests that it is more rationally satisfying, and certainly more in keeping with a viable principle of sufficient reason, to stop searching for causes/explanations at the free choice of the Christian God instead of at the universe itself.
22. Philosophy and Theology: Volume > 27 > Issue: 1
Daniel R. Kern The Logic of Salvation in the Gospel of John
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
I evaluate two claims; that (a) Jesus’s message as recorded in the gospels implies exclusivism with respect to salvation and that, correspondingly, (b) Christians should be exclusivists with respect to salvation. I evaluate these claims through a cataloguing and evaluation of the logical condition involved in each of the claims regarding conditions for salvation made by Jesus in the Gospel of John. As a result, I argue that (a) is false and that, correspondingly, so is (b).
23. Philosophy and Theology: Volume > 27 > Issue: 1
Michael C. Hawley Newman’s Immanent Critique of Liberalism: A Philosophical Argument against Liberal Hubris
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
John Henry Newman's theological arguments against the mixture of liberal philosophy and Christian religion have drawn a great deal of scholarly attention. Comparatively underappreciated is Newman's rebuttal of liberal ideas on the philosophical plane. In this line of argument, which runs parallel to his more purely theological critique, Newman uses some of liberalism's own foundational philosophical premises to undermine the conclusions put forth by the exponents of liberal religion. This immanent critique of liberal religion is important not merely because it shows Newman's capacity to engage his opponents on their own terms, but also because it provides an argument against liberal religion that merits consideration even for those who reject Newman's particular theological beliefs.
24. Philosophy and Theology: Volume > 27 > Issue: 1
W. Chris Hackett Prayer, the Political Problem: Desire, Contemplation, and Models of God
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
This essay attempts to describe some basic aspects of the political logic of religious belief by reference to some recent work of Sarah Coakley. It does so in two parts. First we examine two models of God, the model of “competition,” shared by pop atheism and religious fundamentalism, and the model of “cooperation,” as espoused by classical religious belief. As an explication of this latter model, in the second part we examine what I term the “doxological feminism” of Sarah Coakley as it appears in her recent major work God, Sexuality and the Self. Coakley’s specific insight concerns the intrinsic connection between her religious practice of contemplative prayer and her theoretical reflection on the nature of desire, which is interrogated by reference to the thought of Jean Daniélou.
25. Philosophy and Theology: Volume > 27 > Issue: 1
Roberto Di Ceglie Alvin Plantinga and Thomas Aquinas on Theism and Christianity
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
According to Plantinga, both the theistic and the Christian belief can be affirmed basically, namely, without proofs. Such a position—he tells us—traces back to Aquinas and Calvin. Here I intend to revisit Plantinga’s view of the relation between his own position (as inspired by Calvin) and Aquinas’s. I shall argue that the type of harmony the Reformed philosopher believes to have with Aquinas is only partially present, and that there is a different type of affinity between the two thinkers—though Plantinga is not aware of it. My aim is to show that Aquinas’s thought is really fruitful and inspiring to contemporary philosophy of religion, and that an outstanding thinker of our time such as Plantinga takes it as a reference point although does not entirely capture all its intellectual and spiritual depth.
26. Philosophy and Theology: Volume > 27 > Issue: 1
James B. South Editor's Page
view |  rights & permissions | cited by