Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Browse by:



Displaying: 1-20 of 24 documents


articles
1. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 59 > Issue: 3
Lex Newman The Fourth Meditation
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Recent scholarship suggests that Descartes’s effort to establish a truth criterion is not viciously circular (notwithstanding its reputation)---a fact that invites closer scrutiny of his epistemological program. One of the least well understood features of the project is his deduction of a truth criterion from theistic premises, a demonstration Descartes says he provides in the Fourth Meditation: the alleged proof is not revealed by a casual reading, nor have commentators fared any better; in general, the relevance of the Fourth Meditation has not been duly appreciated. This paper reconstructs the argument of the Fourth Meditation, detailing the steps in the demonstration of the criterion and clarifying its role in the larger program. Surprisingly, Descartes deduces a truth criterion more fundamental than clarity and distinctness; this more fundamental criterion helps explain what are otherwise cryptic (though central) epistemological moves in the Sixth Meditation.
2. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 59 > Issue: 3
Daniel Guevara The Impossibility of Supererogation in Kant’s Moral Theory
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
It is common to think that certain acts are supererogatory, especially certain heroic or saintly self-sacrifices for the good. The idea seems to have an ordinary and clear application. Nothing shows this better than the well-known cases which J. O. Urmson adduced. Urmson argued that no major moral theory could give a proper account of the supererogatory character of such acts, and that therefore none could account for “all the facts of morality,” as he put it. But his arguments were sketchy. This paper shall show, in some detail, that he was essentially right about Kant’s moral theory, and that the criticism goes deep and holds up against recent sympathetic interpretation of Kant’s views of duty and worth.
3. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 59 > Issue: 3
Marc Lange Why Are the Laws of Nature So Important to Science?
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Why should science be so interested in discovering whether p is a law over and above whether p is true? The answer may involve the laws’ relation to counterfactuals: p is a law iff p would still have obtained under any counterfactual supposition that is consistent with the laws. But unless we already understand why science is especially concerned with the laws, we cannot explain why science is especially interested in what would have happened under those counterfactual suppositions consistent with the laws. It is argued that the laws form the only non-trivially “stable” set, where “stability” is invariance under a certain range of counterfactual suppositions not itself defined by reference to the laws. It is then explained why science should be so interested in identifying a non-trivially “stable” set: because of stability’s relation to the best set of “inductive strategies”.
4. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 59 > Issue: 3
Michael J. Zimmerman Virtual Intrinsic Value and the Principle of Organic Unities
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
This paper argues that Moore’s principle of organic unities is false. Advocates of the principle have failed to take note of the distinction between actual intrinsic value and virtual intrinsic value. Purported cases of organic unities, where the actual intrinsic value of a part of a whole is allegedly defeated by the actual intrinsic value of the whole itself, are more plausibly seen as cases where the part in question has no actual intrinsic value but instead a plurality of merely virtual intrinsic values.
5. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 59 > Issue: 3
Luc Bovens The Value of Hope
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Hope obeys Aristotle’s doctrine of the mean: one should neither hope too much, nor too little. But what determines what constitutes too much and what constitutes too little for a particular person at a particular time? The sceptic presents an argument to the effect that it is never rational to hope. An attempt to answer the sceptic leads us in different directions. Decision-theoretic and preference-theoretic arguments support the instrumental value of hope. An investigation into the nature of hope permits us to assess the intrinsic value of hope. However, it must be granted to the sceptic that there is a tension between hope and epistemic rationality. I conclude with some reflections about the relationship between hope and character features that are constitutive of inner strength.
discussions
6. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 59 > Issue: 3
Duncan Mcfarland Mark Johnston’s Substitution Principle: A New Counterexample?
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
According to a subjectivist view of some concept, C, there is an a priori implication of subjective responses in C’s application or possession conditions. Subjectivists who intend their view to be descriptive of our practice with C will hold that it is possible for there to be true empirical claims which explain such responses in terms of certain things being C. Mark Johnston’s “missing-explanation argument’ employs a substitution principle with a view to establishing that these strands of subjectivism are inconsistent. I suggest that Johnston’s substitution principle survives an attempt by Alex Miller to show that it is unreliable, but that it is prey to a counterexample which cannot be explained away by the proponent of the missing-explanation argument. I conclude that the missing-explanation argument poses no threat to subjectivism.
7. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 59 > Issue: 3
Oron Shagrir More on Global Supervenience
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Jaegwon Kim contends that global supervenience is consistent with non-materialistic cases. Paull and Sider, Horgan, as well as Kim, attempt to defend it from these charges. It is shown here that their defense is only partially successful. Their defense meets one challenge to global supervenience---the hydrogen-atom case---but fails to meet other, ‘local’, cases. It is suggested that the other challenges can be met if global supervenience is combined with weak supervenience. The combination of global and weak supervenience constitutes a viable picture of psychophysical relations, and is especially attractive to nonreductive materialists who are also anti-individualists.
8. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 59 > Issue: 3
Jonathan L. Kvanvig Lewis on Finkish Dispositions
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Finkish dispositions, those dispositions that are lost when their conditions of realization occur, pose deep problems for counterfactual accounts of dispositions. David Lewis has argued that the counterfactual approach can be rescued, offering such an account that purports to handle finkish as well as other dispositions. The paper argues that Lewis’s account fails to account for several kinds of dispositions, one of which involves failure to distinguish parallel processes from unitary processes.
symposia
9. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 59 > Issue: 3
Cynthia Macdonald Shoemaker on Self-Knowledge and Inner Sense
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
What is introspective know ledge of one’s own intentional states like? This paper aims to make plausible the view that certain cases of self-knowledge, namely the cogito-type ones, are enough like perception to count as cases of quasi-observation. To this end it considers the highly influential arguments developed by Sydney Shoemaker in his recent Royce Lectures. These present the most formidable challenge to the view that certain cases of self-knowledge are quasi-observational and so deserve detailed examination. Shoemaker’s arguments are directed against two models of ordinary perception, the “object perception model” and the “broad perceptual model”. I argue that the core theses that Shoemaker associated with them are either dubious in their own right or applicable to certain cases of self-knowledge. Overall the aim is to show that there is such a variety of patterns in each case that simple analogies or disanalogies are unhelpful.
10. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 59 > Issue: 3
Sydney Shoemaker Reply to Cynthia Macdonald
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
11. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 59 > Issue: 3
Shannon Densmore, Daniel Dennett The Virtues of Virtual Machines
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
12. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 59 > Issue: 3
Paul M. Churchland Densmore and Dennett on Virtual Machines and Consciousness
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
13. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 59 > Issue: 3
Alastair Norcross Intransitivity and the Person-Affecting Principle
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Philosophy journals and conferences have recently seen several attempts to argue that ‘all-things-considered better than’ does not obey strict transitivity. This paper focuses on Larry Temkin’s argument in “Intransitivity and the Mere Addition Paradox.” Although his argument is not aimed just at utilitarians or even consequentialists in general, it is of particular significance to consequentialists. If ‘all-things-considered better than’ does not obey transitivity, there may be choice situations in which there is no optimal choice, which would seem to open the door to a consequentialist account of moral dilemmas. Temkin’s argument crucially appeals to what he calls “the Person-Affecting Principle (PAP)”. which he roughly characterizes as follows, “On PAP, one outcome is worse than another only if it affects people for the worse” This paper argues that PAP, although plausible, does not hold in precisely those situations in which it would have to hold in order for Temkin’s argument against transitivity to work.
14. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 59 > Issue: 3
Larry S. Temkin Intransitivity and the Person-Affecting Principle: A Response
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
book symposium:
15. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 59 > Issue: 3
Martha C. Nussbaum Précis of The Therapy of Desire
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
16. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 59 > Issue: 3
John Martin Fischer Contribution on Martha Nussbaum’s The Therapy of Desire
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
17. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 59 > Issue: 3
Robert C. Roberts Emotions as Judgments
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
18. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 59 > Issue: 3
Richard Sorabji Therapy of Desire
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
19. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 59 > Issue: 3
Brad Inwood Truth in Moral Medicine
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
20. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 59 > Issue: 3
Martha C. Nussbaum Reply to Papers in Symposium on Nussbaum, The Therapy of Desire
view |  rights & permissions | cited by