Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Browse by:



Displaying: 61-80 of 97 documents


discussion
61. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 58 > Issue: 2
Anthony Brueckner Shoemaker on Second-Order Belief
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In a number of papers, Sydney Shoemaker has argued that first-order belief plus rationality implies second-order belief. This paper is a critical discussion of Shoemaker’s argument.
book symposium:
62. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 58 > Issue: 2
John McDowell Précis of Mind and World
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
63. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 58 > Issue: 2
Robert Brandom Perception and Rational Constraint
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
64. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 58 > Issue: 2
Arthur W. Collins Beastly Experience
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
65. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 58 > Issue: 2
Christopher Peacocke Nonconceptual Content Defended
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
66. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 58 > Issue: 2
Richard Rorty McDowell, Davidson, and Spontaneity
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
67. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 58 > Issue: 2
Crispin Wright McDowell’s Oscillation
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
68. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 58 > Issue: 2
John McDowell Reply to Commentators
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
69. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 58 > Issue: 2
Galen Strawson Précis of Mental Reality
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
70. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 58 > Issue: 2
Noam Chomsky Comments: Galen Strawson, Mental Reality
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
71. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 58 > Issue: 2
Pierre Jacob What Is the Phenomenology of Thought?
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
72. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 58 > Issue: 2
Michael Smith Galen Strawson and the Weather Watchers
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
73. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 58 > Issue: 2
Paul F. Snowdon Strawson’s Agnostic Materialism
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
74. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 58 > Issue: 2
Galen Strawson Replies to Noam Chomsky, Pierre Jacob, Michael Smith, and Paul Snowdon
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
critical notices
75. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 58 > Issue: 2
Judith Wagner Decew Innocence Lost: An Examination of Inescapable Moral Wrongdoing
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
76. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 58 > Issue: 2
David E. Cooper Aesthetic Value
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
articles
77. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 58 > Issue: 1
Valerie Gray Hardcastle On the Matter of Minds and Mental Causation
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
There is a difference between someone breaking a glass by accidentally brushing up against it and smashing a glass in a fit of anger. In the first case, the person’s cognitive state has little to do with the event, but in the second, the mental state qua anger is quite relevant. How are we to understand this difference? What is the proper way to understand the relation between the mind, the brain, and the resultant behavior? This paper explores the popular “middle ground” reply in which mental phenomena are claimed to be “as real as” other higher level properties. It argues that this solution fails to answer epistemological difficulties surrounding how to chose the appropriate factors in an explanation. A more sophisticated understanding of scientific theorizing and of the relation between ontology and explanation give us a framework in which we can determine when we should refer to mental states as being the causally efficacious agents for some behavior.
78. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 58 > Issue: 1
Eugene Mills The Unity of Justification
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
The thesis that practical and epistemic justification can diverge---that it can be reasonable to believe something, all things considered, even when believing is epistemically unjustified, and the reverse---is widely accepted. I argue that this acceptance is unfounded. I show, first, that examples of the sort typically cited as straightforwardly illustrative of the “divergence thesis” do not, in fact, support it. The view to the contrary derives from conflating the assessment of acts which cause one to believe with the assessment of believing itself. I argue, too, that the divergence thesis cannot be rescued by appeal to the possibility of doxastic voluntarism. Finally, I argue that the general acceptance of the divergence thesis rests on a conception of justification, both practical and epistemic, which is seriously flawed.
79. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 58 > Issue: 1
Martine Nida-Rümelin On Belief About Experiences: An Epistemological Distinction Applied to the Knowledge Argument Against Physicalism
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
The article introduces two kinds of belief-phenomenal belief and nonphenomenal belief---about color experiences and examines under what conditions the distinction can be extended to belief about other kinds of mental states. A thesis of the paper is that the so-called Knowledge Argument should not be formulated---as usual---using the locution of ‘knowing what it’s like’ but instead using the concept of phenomenal belief and explains why ‘knowing what it's like’ does not serve the purposes of those who wish to defend the Knowledge Argument. The article distinguishes two rival accounts of the phenomenal/nonphenomenal distinction and explains how the result of the Knowledge Argument depends upon which of these accounts one wishes to accept.
80. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 58 > Issue: 1
Roy A. Sorensen Self-Strengthening Empathy
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Stepping into the other guy’s shoes works best when you resemble him. After all, the procedure is to use yourself as a model: in goes hypothetical beliefs and desires, out comes hypothetical actions and revised beliefs and desires. If you are structurally analogous to the empathee, then accurate inputs generate accurate outputs---just as with any other simulation. The greater the degree of isomorphism, the more dependable and precise the results. This sensitivity to degrees of resemblance suggests that the method of empathy works best for average people. The advantage of being a small but representative sample of the population will create a bootstrap effect. For as average people prosper, there will be more average descendants and so the degree of resemblance in subsequent generations will snowball. Each increment in like-mindedness further enhances the reliability and validity of mental simulation. With each circuit along the spiral, there is tighter and tighter bunching and hence further empowerment of empathy. The method is self-strengthening and eventually molds a population of hyper-similar individuals---which partly solves the problem of other minds.