Cover of The Review of Metaphysics
Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Browse by:



Displaying: 21-40 of 135 documents


book reviews
21. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 66 > Issue: 4
Walker Page Reeve, C. D. C., Action, Contemplation, and Happiness: An Essay on Aristotle
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
22. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 66 > Issue: 4
Marie I. George Rist, John M., Plato’s Moral Realism: The Discovery of the Presuppositions of Ethics
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
23. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 66 > Issue: 4
Colin Marshall Skorupski, John., The Domain of Reasons
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
24. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 66 > Issue: 4
Samantha E. Thompson Sorabji, Richard., Gandhi and the Stoics: Modern Experiments on Ancient Values
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
25. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 66 > Issue: 4
Gaven Kerr, O.P. Stroud, Barry., Engagement and Metaphysical Dissatisfaction: Modality and Value
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
26. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 66 > Issue: 4
Michael R. Spicher Tamen, Miguel., What Art Is Like, in Constant Reference to the Alice Books
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
27. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 66 > Issue: 4
Dorothea Olkowski Verschuuren, Gerard M., Darwin’s Philosophical Legacy, The Good and the Not-So-Good
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
28. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 66 > Issue: 4
Robert L’Arrivee Weierter, Stuart., Understanding Life and Death through Plato and Socrates: Philosophy As a Confrontation with Eternity
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
29. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 66 > Issue: 4
Reviewer Index
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
30. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 66 > Issue: 4
Blaise Blain and Staff Recent Titles in Philosophy
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
31. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 66 > Issue: 4
Abstracts
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
32. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 66 > Issue: 4
Announcements
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
33. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 66 > Issue: 4
Yearly Index
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
articles
34. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 66 > Issue: 3
Wouter Goris De Magistro - Thomas Aquinas, Henry of Ghent, and John Duns Scotus on Natural Conceptions
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
35. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 66 > Issue: 3
Ray Liikanen Beyond Kant and Hegel
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Despite the opinion held by some that Kant’s Critical philosophy is no longer relevant this essay shows that the problems it deals with are ever present. Kant’s critical insights into these problems can be revealed by citing his open invitation to his critical reader to devote to the first antinomy his chief attention. This paper cites Hegel’s response to this invitation and shows where Hegel failed to meet with Kant’s critical demands. An analogous resolution is proposed that falls in line not only with Kant, but with the science of big bang cosmology. An open as opposed to a closed interpretation of Kant is also argued for that leads to the judgment that Kant did not attempt to put an end to speculative metaphysics, but rather, he attempted to inspire metaphysicians to the end of a science of metaphysics.
36. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 66 > Issue: 3
James A. Clarke Fichte’s Critique of Rousseau
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
37. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 66 > Issue: 3
Michael Schlie Words without Desire: Hegel, Strauss, and Political Violence
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
38. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 66 > Issue: 3
Herman De Dijn Spinoza on Truth, Religion, and Salvation
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
According to Spinoza, the implications of the new scientific worldview of his time are diametrically opposed to the fundamental philosophical-theological tenets of traditional thought and religion. Yet, paradoxically, this does not bring him to the rejection of the notion of God (atheism), of notions of good and bad (cynicism), or even of ordinary religion (anti-religion). On the contrary, his philosophy as a whole can be seen as a radical reconsideration of religion in the light of the modern situation, and not at all as an exit from it. In line with the new science, Spinoza develops a new metaphysics centered on the notion Deus sive Natura (and not simply Natura), a new rational ethics (Ethics IV), and a new philosophical religion (Ethics V). The new philosophical religion, being at the same time the culmination of the ethical life, is based upon the non-anthropomorphic, but still somehow transcendent, notion of God, the one substance with infinite attributes, radically different from the modes, both finite and infinite. In the final part of this article, an attempt is made to acquire some form of inside perspective on what Spinoza may mean by true religion as consisting in amor Dei intellectualis. Anticipating Hume, Spinoza considers ordinary religion as a natural phenomenon, which he studies in detail in his Tractatus Theologico-politicus. Unlike later Enlightenment thinkers, he distinguishes between superstition and purified religion, and accepts that the latter can bring a specific kind of salvation for the common people.
book reviews
39. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 66 > Issue: 3
John R. Fortin, O.S.B. Asiedu, F. B. A., From Augustine to Anselm: The Influence of “De Trinitate” on the “Monologion
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
40. The Review of Metaphysics: Volume > 66 > Issue: 3
Jeffrey L. Powell Braver, Lee., Groundless Grounds: A Study of Wittgenstein and Heidegger
view |  rights & permissions | cited by