Cover of Social Theory and Practice
Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Browse by:



Displaying: 21-40 of 45 documents


book reviews
21. Social Theory and Practice: Volume > 40 > Issue: 3
Kelly McCormick D. Justin Coates and Neal A. Tognazzini (eds.), Blame: Its Nature and Norms
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
22. Social Theory and Practice: Volume > 40 > Issue: 3
George Schedler James P. Sterba, From Rationality to Equality
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
23. Social Theory and Practice: Volume > 40 > Issue: 2
Eldon Soifer, David Elliott Nonstandard Observers and the Nature of Privacy
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Observation by nonstandard observers (such as cats) has different implications for privacy than observation by ordinary human beings. This seemingly trivial point yields important insights about privacy. Searching for the characteristic that explains this difference reveals that privacy is importantly related to our interest in how others see us, and the derivative interest in controlling the information upon which others’ perceptions are based. This also casts light on the important relationships between privacy, autonomy, and the development of public personae.
24. Social Theory and Practice: Volume > 40 > Issue: 2
Thomas M. Besch On Discursive Respect
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Constructivism often expresses a commitment to discursive respect. The paper explores interdependencies between three dimensions of discursive respect, namely, its depth, scope, and purchase. It identifies challenges for constructivist attempts to locate discursive respect in the normative space defined by these dimensions, and considers whether there can be a coherent conception of discursive respect that is plausibly deep, inclusive in scope, and meaningfully rich in purchase. I suggest that locating discursive respect within the matrix of discursive inclusion is a task partly beyond constructivism, especially if discursive respect, or the constitutive discursive standing that it accords, is an important good.
25. Social Theory and Practice: Volume > 40 > Issue: 2
Iñigo González-Ricoy The Republican Case for Workplace Democracy
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
The republican case for workplace democracy (WD) is presented and defended from two alternative means of ensuring freedom from arbitrary interference in the firm—namely, (a) the right to freely exit the firm and (b) workplace regulation. This paper shows, respectively, that costless exit is neither possible nor desirable in either perfect or imperfect labor markets, and that managerial discretion is both desirable and inevitable due to the incompleteness of employment contracts and labor legislation. The paper then shows that WD is necessary, from a republican standpoint, if workers’ interests are to be adequately tracked in the exercise of managerial authority. Three important objections are finally addressed—(i) that WD is redundant, (ii) that it is unnecessary provided that litigation and unionism can produce similar outcomes, and (iii) that it falls short of ensuring republican freedom compared to self-employment.
26. Social Theory and Practice: Volume > 40 > Issue: 2
Paul Morrow Mass Atrocity and Manipulation of Social Norms
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Mass atrocities are commonly explained in terms of changes in legal or moral norms. This paper examines the role that changes in social norms can play in precipitating or prolonging mass atrocities. I focus specifically on manipulative transformations of social norms. I first distinguish between the manipulative introduction and the manipulative activation of social norms. I then explain how both forms of manipulation can contribute to mass atrocities. Finally, extending a line of thought first suggested by Hannah Arendt, I present a case study of the manipulative introduction and activation of language rules amongst the Nazis during World War Two.
27. Social Theory and Practice: Volume > 40 > Issue: 2
Ewan Kingston Climate Justice and Temporally Remote Emissions
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Many suggest that we should look backward and measure the differences among various parties’ past emissions of greenhouse gases to allocate moral responsibility to remedy climate change. Such backward-looking approaches face two key objections: that previous emitters were unaware of the consequences of their actions, and that the emitters who should be held responsible have disappeared. I assess several arguments that try to counter these objections: the argument from strict liability, arguments that the beneficiary of harmful or unjust emissions should pay, and arguments from distributive justice. I argue that none of these successfully justify a backward-looking approach to the temporally remote portion of the climate burden.
28. Social Theory and Practice: Volume > 40 > Issue: 2
Tamar Meisels Fighting for Independence: What Can Just War Theory Learn from Civil Conflict?
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
The purpose of this article is twofold. First, it presents the urgent case of civil war, relatively undertheorized by just war theorists, along with the normative issues that pertain to this type of conflict and its participants specifically. Second, it suggests that this civil war perspective offers fresh support for the traditional “independence thesis”— separating just cause for war from the rules of its conduct—which is often criticized by contemporary moral philosophers.
book reviews
29. Social Theory and Practice: Volume > 40 > Issue: 2
Christine M. Koggel Sarah Clark Miller, The Ethics of Need: Agency, Dignity, and Obligation
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
30. Social Theory and Practice: Volume > 40 > Issue: 2
Linda Nicholson Allison Weir, Identities and Freedom: Feminist Theory Between Power and Connection
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
31. Social Theory and Practice: Volume > 40 > Issue: 2
Lara Denis Thomas E. Hill, Jr., Virtue, Rules, and Justice: Kantian Aspirations
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
32. Social Theory and Practice: Volume > 40 > Issue: 2
Paul Bloomfield Daniel C. Russell, Happiness for Humans
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
33. Social Theory and Practice: Volume > 40 > Issue: 2
Lorraine Besser-Jones Lawrence Becker, Habilitation, Health, and Agency: A Framework for Basic Justice
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
34. Social Theory and Practice: Volume > 40 > Issue: 1
Roberto Frega The Normative Creature: Toward a Practice-Based Account of Normativity
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In this paper I offer a first account of a practice-based conception of normativity for the political domain. This standpoint is used to relocate the most sophisticated normative practices of justification and critique within an experience-based framework, that of the human being as a “normative creature.” I begin by discussing the two major paradigms in political theory, showing that their neglect of this broad framework of normativity is a serious drawback. I then proceed to articulate the central elements of a practicebased account of normativity: the notions of normative practices and normative orders, and an account of the rationality potential of normativity as practice.
35. Social Theory and Practice: Volume > 40 > Issue: 1
S. D. John Risk, Contractualism, and Rose's "Prevention Paradox"
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Geoffrey Rose’s prevention paradox points to a tension between two prima facie plausible moral principles: that we should save the greater number and that weshould save the most at risk. This paper argues that a novel moral theory, ex-ante contractualism, captures our intuitions in many prevention paradox cases, regardless of our interpretation of probability claims. However, it goes on to show that it might be impossible to square ex-ante contractualism with all of our moral intuitions. It concludes that even if ex-ante contractualism cannot furnish an entire ethics of risk, it does identify important considerations for any such theory.
36. Social Theory and Practice: Volume > 40 > Issue: 1
Robert Jubb Participation in and Responsibility for State Injustices
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
This paper discusses the criteria for acceptably holding citizens partly responsible for wrongs their state or its agents commit. Some proposed criteria are not, it argues, appropriately sensitive to the particular coercive relation between state and citizen. Others, which are, conceive of it wrongly and fail to match our judgments about a range of cases. Alternative criteria of breadth and joint authorship, built around Christopher Kutz's account of participation, better match these considered judgments as well as linking them to a more powerful theoretical framework. Understanding citizens' responsibility will mean understanding these criteria more fully.
37. Social Theory and Practice: Volume > 40 > Issue: 1
D. C. Matthew Purview and Permissibility: The Site of Justice and the Case of Private Racial Discrimination
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
If there is a “basic structure objection” (BSO) to G.A. Cohen’s incentive critique of Rawls, then there is also a BSO to claims that private racial discrimination thwarts social justice by reducing the opportunity of its targets. In this paper, I take up the debate about the site or purview of justice and discuss it with reference to the case of race. I argue that the dispute about the site of justice has been wrongly understood as a dispute about the substantive requirements of justice instead of as a dispute about where it is appropriate to apply considerations of justice.
38. Social Theory and Practice: Volume > 40 > Issue: 1
Tobey Scharding Income Inequalities in a Context of Political Equality: Guaranteed Basic Income, No Guaranteed Income, or Guaranteed Work Opportunities
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
This paper investigates individual differences-based income entitlements (entitlements based on people’s contributions, efforts, and needs) in a context of political equality. Three regimes for distributing income are considered: guaranteed basic income (GBI), no guaranteed income (NGI), and guaranteed work opportunities (GWO). Whereas GBI attends to equality while remaining silent on difference and NGI attends to difference while de-emphasizing equality, GWO attends to both difference and equality. Balancing individual differences and political equality is a plausible goal for distributive justice, and the GWO regime seems well suited to accommodate these joint concerns.
39. Social Theory and Practice: Volume > 40 > Issue: 1
Luara Ferracioli The Appeal and Danger of a New Refugee Convention
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
It is widely held that the current refugee Convention is inadequate with respect to its specification of who counts as a refugee and in its assignment of responsibility concerning refugees to states. At the same time, there is substantial agreement among scholars that the negotiation of a new Convention would lead states to extricate themselves from previously assumed responsibilities rather than sign on to a set of more desirable legal norms. In this paper, I argue that states should ultimately negotiate a new Convention, but that first they must alleviate the institutional and motivational constraints that make progress currently unattainable.
book reviews
40. Social Theory and Practice: Volume > 40 > Issue: 1
Michael D. Burroughs Sally Haslanger, "Resisting Reality: Social Construction and Social Critique"
view |  rights & permissions | cited by