Cover of Southwest Philosophy Review
Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Browse by:



Displaying: 21-40 of 57 documents


commentaries
21. Southwest Philosophy Review: Volume > 39 > Issue: 2
Cheryl Abbate Comments on “Epistemic Involuntarism and Undesirable Beliefs” by Deborah Heikes
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
22. Southwest Philosophy Review: Volume > 39 > Issue: 2
Songyao Ren Commentary on Green’s “Recalcitrant Beliefs and Epistemic Akrasia”
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
23. Southwest Philosophy Review: Volume > 39 > Issue: 2
John R. Harris Utilitarianism, Derivative Obligations, and the Problem of Political Obligation
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
24. Southwest Philosophy Review: Volume > 39 > Issue: 2
Sarah Woolwine Comments on Josué Piñeiro “Rilkean Memory and Testimonial Injustice”
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
open submission articles
25. Southwest Philosophy Review: Volume > 39 > Issue: 2
Miles Hentrup Skepticism and Negativity in Hegel’s Philosophy
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
26. Southwest Philosophy Review: Volume > 39 > Issue: 2
Tori Helen Cotton The Problem With Who I Know: What Contextualism Can Tell Us About Interpersonal Knowledge Claims
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
27. Southwest Philosophy Review: Volume > 39 > Issue: 2
Domenica Romagni Descartes On Referring the Passions
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
As suggested by the title, Descartes’ Passions of the Soul deals primarily with states of the soul that he calls ‘passions.’ This designation includes all mental states that are actively caused by the body and passively received by the soul. However, as Descartes points out to the reader, there is a more specialized or proper usage of ‘passion’ that picks out a subclass of these and which aligns more-or-less with what we might now call ‘emotions.’ In this paper, I will address how Descartes classifies these ‘proper passions,’ paying special attention to how he distinguishes them from the other species of the passions in general. One of my primary aims will be to highlight an under-appreciated feature of the proper passions; namely, that they are distinct from other perceptions in their systematic divergence in terms of their distal or ‘first’ cause, their intentional object, and how they are ‘referred.’ After arguing for this distinctive feature of the proper passions, I show how it enables Descartes to provide a nuanced and multi-faceted account of our emotional experiences that incorporates external sensory perceptions, internal or bodily perceptions, and various cognitive assessments.
book review
28. Southwest Philosophy Review: Volume > 39 > Issue: 2
Josef Novák Review of The Selected Writings of Jan Patočka: Care for the Soul
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
29. Southwest Philosophy Review: Volume > 39 > Issue: 1
Ken Rogerson Memorial Notice: Past President Don Marquis, 1935-2022
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
articles
30. Southwest Philosophy Review: Volume > 39 > Issue: 1
Paul Carron The Moral Threat of Profound Loneliness (Presidential Address)
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
31. Southwest Philosophy Review: Volume > 39 > Issue: 1
David Skowronski Cryptobiosis and Composition (Presidential Prize Award Winner)
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
32. Southwest Philosophy Review: Volume > 39 > Issue: 1
Spencer Ivy Getting Sophisticated: In Favor of Hybrid Views of Skilled Action in Expertise
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
The long history of research and debate surrounding expertise has emphasized the importance of both automaticity and intelligent deliberation in the control of skilled, expert action – and often, their mutual exclusion of one another. To the contrary, recent developments in the cognitive science of skill implicate the likelihood of a third, hybrid line of interpretation and a new path forward. This paper surveys these recent developments, arguing that hybrid models of expertise and skill are the most fruitful way forward in interpreting and conducting research on experts. I categorize a new set of interpretations of skill as ‘sophisticated hybrid models’ owing to the fact that they deny the mutual exclusion of automaticity from intelligent action control. I then argue that this interpretive strategy is the most fruitful way forward to making clear much of the complexity of skilled action and expertise.
33. Southwest Philosophy Review: Volume > 39 > Issue: 1
Jordan van den Hoonaard Defending Heidegger Against the Charge of Correlationism: A Prolegomena to a Phenomenology of Nature
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
34. Southwest Philosophy Review: Volume > 39 > Issue: 1
Eric Wilkinson Mersenne’s Principles of Song Creation
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
35. Southwest Philosophy Review: Volume > 39 > Issue: 1
Charles Joshua Horn The Ontological Interpretation of Leibniz’s Account of Compossibility
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
36. Southwest Philosophy Review: Volume > 39 > Issue: 1
Andrew Burnside Actual Infinity: Spinoza’s Substance Monism as a Reply to Aristotle’s Physics
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
I conceive of Spinoza’s substance monism as a response to Aristotle’s prohibition against actual infinity for one key reason: nature, being all things, is necessarily infi nite. Spinoza encapsulates his substance monism with the phrase, “Deus sive Natura,” implying that there is only one infinite substance, which also possesses an infi nity of attributes, of which we are but modes. These logical delineations of substance never actually break up God’s reality. Aristotle’s well-known argument against the reality of an actual infinity in his Physics prohibits the existence of an actually infinite bodily substance because it would necessarily “destroy” (Physics 204b26-27) all other elements or bodies. On Aristotle’s view, there is a fundamental and concrete distinction between things: each substance is primarily a this (Categories 3b10). I maintain that Spinoza’s rationalism and radicalization of the principle of sufficient reason lends him greater explanatory potential than Aristotle to justify the (non) existence of actual infinity.
37. Southwest Philosophy Review: Volume > 39 > Issue: 1
T. Baker The Euthyphro Problem in Plato’s Cratylus
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
38. Southwest Philosophy Review: Volume > 39 > Issue: 1
Pete LeGrant The Democritean Descent: A Reply to Della Rocca’s The Parmenidean Ascent
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
39. Southwest Philosophy Review: Volume > 39 > Issue: 1
Tuomas W. Manninen A New Old Challenge to Theories of Personhood: The Curious Cases of Feral Children
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Although fantastical thought-experiments about personal identity abound, these seemingly cannot bring home the conviction one way or the other, when it comes to the nature of diachronic (or synchronic) personhood. Per Kathleen Wilkes, these thought-experiments suffer from being divorced from the necessary background conditions. In this paper, I aim to rectify this by developing an empirically-informed thought experiment (that fill in these blanks) focusing on feral children, or children who have grown up in near-complete isolation from all human interaction. After detailing the significance of these cases and discussing a present-day case, I move to construct the background for thought-experiments on these cases. As an upshot, I apply the experiment to a contemporary theory of personhood (namely, constitutionalism), analyze its shortcomings, and make recommendations for future improvements.
40. Southwest Philosophy Review: Volume > 39 > Issue: 1
Bertha Alvarez Manninen Respecting Fetal Life Within Pro-choice Advocacy: Conceding to Some Pro-life Concerns (and Asking the Same in Return)
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
This paper will explain three reasons why pro-choice advocates should move away from arguments in favor of abortion choice that is dependent upon the fetus’ non-personhood, and more towards generating arguments in favor of abortion choice that embraces a more respectful view of fetal life. First, the future of the legal right to an abortion in the United States may depend on generating an argument that does not rely on denying fetal personhood. Second, pro-choice advocates should be more respectful of fetal life because the hesitancy of doing so has not gone over well in the general public. Even individuals who are sympathetic to a pro-choice perspective are sometimes hesitant to align themselves with the pro-choice community because of the perception that it is antithetical to the value of fetal life. The third reason is that some women who choose abortion regard it as a morally significant act precisely because they regard the fetus as a morally significant being.