Cover of Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science
Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Browse by:



Displaying: 61-80 of 1756 documents


articles
61. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 36 > Issue: 3
Uku Tooming Politics of Folk Psychology: Believing what Others Believe
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In this paper, I argue that by attributing beliefs the attributer is pushed toward taking a stand on the content of those beliefs and that what stand they take partially depends on the relationship between the attributer and the attributee. In particular, if the attributee enjoys a higher social standing than the attributer, the latter is disposed to adopt the attributed belief, as long as certain other conditions are met. I will call this view the Adoption-by-Attribution model. Because of the non-epistemic influence that derives from the relation of inequality, belief attribution can reinforce the existing unequal power relations and contribute to epistemic injustice.
62. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 36 > Issue: 3
Bruno Borge, Nicolás Lo Guercio Learning from Scientific Disagreement
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
The article addresses the question of how should scientific peers revise their beliefs (if at all) upon recognized disagreement. After presenting the basics of peer disagreement in sections 1 and 2, we focus, in section 3, on a concrete case of scientific disagreement, to wit, the dispute over the evidential status of randomized control trials in medical practice. The examination of this case motivates the idea that some scientific disagreements permit a steadfast reaction. In section 4, we support this conclusion by providing a normative argument in the same direction; if we are correct, typical reasons for conciliation are absent in this kind of scientific disagreements.
63. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 36 > Issue: 3
Javier Anta The epistemic schism of statistical mechanics
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In this paper I will argue that the two main approaches to statistical mechanics, that of Boltzmann and Gibbs, constitute two substantially different theoretical apparatuses. Particularly, I defend that this theoretical split must be philosophically understood as a separation of epistemic functions within this physical domain: while Boltzmannians are able to generate powerful explanations of thermal phenomena from molecular dynamics, Gibbsians can statistically predict observable values in a highly effective way. Therefore, statistical mechanics is a counterexample to Hempel’s (1958) symmetry thesis, where the predictive capacity of a theory is directly correlated with its explanatory potential and vice versa.
64. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 36 > Issue: 3
Miguel Escribano Cabeza La idea de epigénesis en la obra de W. Harvey. Una lectura organicista
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
This paper takes an organicist perspective of W. Harvey’s conception of epigenesis in his work Exercitationes de generatione animalium (1651). In line with this reading, I provide a critical assessment of the different interpretations (mechanistic or vitalist) of Harvey’s idea of epigenesis. The English physician develops his conception of embryogenesis as a process that cannot be understood from the categories of human art, as is apparent in his criticisms towards his teacher, Fabricius. Nor is it accurate to say that his position is animistic. An immersion in this last question will show us his organic conception of the soul, as an extension of the Aristotelian-Galenic tradition.
65. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 36 > Issue: 3
Summary
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
66. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 36 > Issue: 3
Contents of Volume 36
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
monographic section
67. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 36 > Issue: 2
Valeriano Iranzo Guest editor’s presentation
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
68. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 36 > Issue: 2
Harold Kincaid Mechanisms, good and bad
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
The claim that mechanisms are essential good science is widespread. I argue, however, that these claims are ambiguous in multiple ways. I sort out different version of the mechanism idea: (1) mechanisms that are horizontal —between cause and effect— and mechanisms that are vertical —they realize in lower-level terms causal properties—: and (2) different purposes or uses mechanisms may have. I then focus on the claim that various senses of mechanism are necessary for the confirmation of causal claims. The paper shows that mechanisms can be useful, essential, or harmful depending on context, using the now standard graphical causal structure framework. These conclusions also support the larger philosophy of science moral that methodological norms in science are often context specific and empirical, not a priori and universal.
69. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 36 > Issue: 2
Jon Williamson The feasibility and malleability of EBM+
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
The EBM+ programme is an attempt to improve the way in which present-day evidence-based medicine (EBM) assesses causal claims: according to EBM+, mechanistic studies should be scrutinised alongside association studies. This paper addresses two worries about EBM+: (i) that it is not feasible in practice, and (ii) that it is too malleable, i.e., its results depend on subjective choices that need to be made in order to implement the procedure. Several responses to these two worries are considered and evaluated. The paper also discusses the question of whether we should have confidence in medical interventions, in the light of Stegenga’s arguments for medical nihilism.
70. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 36 > Issue: 2
Saúl Pérez-González, Valeriano Iranzo Assessing the role of evidence of mechanisms in causal extrapolation
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Extrapolation of causal claims from study populations to other populations of interest is a problematic issue. The standard approach in experimental research, which prioritises randomized controlled trials and statistical evidence, is not devoid of difficulties. Granted that, it has been defended that evidence of mechanisms is indispensable for causal extrapolation. We argue, contrarily, that this sort of evidence is not indispensable. Nonetheless, we also think that occasionally it may be helpful. In order to clarify its relevance, we introduce a distinction between a positive and a negative role of evidence of mechanisms. Our conclusion is that the former is highly questionable, but the latter may be a trustworthy resource for causal extrapolation.
articles
71. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 36 > Issue: 2
Eduardo Pérez-Navarro No matter who: What makes one a relativist?
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
As part of her argument that relativism and contextualism are nothing but notational variants of each other, Stojanovic holds that contextualism is flexible enough to achieve whatever relativism might do if the matter is what truth-value is assigned to each pair of sentence and context. In this paper, I reply to this statement by arguing that contextualism cannot be made as flexible as relativism without in fact turning it into a version of relativism. The key to my response to Stojanovic is that, while relativism relativizes utterance truth, contextualism does not, so parameters that are not fixed at the context of utterance will be accessible for the relativist, but not for the contextualist. Although the relativity of utterance truth follows as soon as propositional truth is relativized to contexts of assessment, as the relativist does, it is easy to lose sight of this fact if we identify the context of assessment with the assessor’s context. Hence, the point of this paper is that the difference between relativism and contextualism is not one as to whose parameters play a role in determining the sentence’s truth-value. If it were, contextualism could indeed be made just as flexible as relativism.
72. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 36 > Issue: 2
David Pineda-Oliva Defending the motivational theory of desire
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In this paper I offer a defense of the motivational theory of desire. According to the motivational view, a desire is basically a disposition to bring about the desire’s content. First, I argue that two rival views on the nature of desire, the evaluative theory and the deontic theory, fall prey to the problem of the death of desire and that, when one tries to develop a plausible version of these theories which is able to overcome this problem, one ends up with a view that is not relevantly different from the evaluative view. Second, I respond to some objections to the claim that motivations are sufficient for desire, namely, the Radioman objection and the objection that some motivational states like intentions and habits are not desires.
73. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 36 > Issue: 2
Timm Lampert Newton’s experimental proofs
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Newton claims that his theorems in the Opticks are derived from experiments alone. The paper explains this dictum by relating Newton’s proof method to an iconic conception of proof as opposed to a symbolic one. Theorems are not derived from hypotheses; instead properties of light are identified by experimental properties based on rules of inductive reasoning.
book reviews
74. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 36 > Issue: 2
David Teira Adolfo Garcia de la Sienra (2019). A Structuralist Theory of Economics
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
75. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 36 > Issue: 2
Summary
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
articles
76. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 36 > Issue: 1
Francesca Poggiolesi, Nissim Francez Towards a generalization of the logic of grounding
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
The main goal of this paper is to provide a ground-analysis of two classical connectives that have so far been ignored in the literature, namely the exclusive disjunction, and the ternary disjunction. Such ground-analysis not only serves to extend the applicability of the logic of grounding but also leads to a generalization of Poggiolesi (2016)’s definition of the notion of complete and immediate grounding.
77. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 36 > Issue: 1
Ezequiel Zerbudis Making sense of the ‘is’ of constitution
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
I consider a problem that arises in connection with (alleged) cases of coincident objects (such as a statue and the lump of clay it is made of) and that affects the two main accounts that have been given of such cases, namely, Pluralism (according to which statue and lump are distinct) and Monism (according to which they are one). The problem is that both views seem committed to accepting strained interpretations of some of the statements used to describe the situation. I consider Pickel’s arguments against the Pluralist’s strategy of interpreting ‘is’ as expressing constitution in sentences such as ‘The statue is the lump of clay’, and provide reasons for rejecting them—so as to vindicate, eventually, the Pluralist position.
78. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 36 > Issue: 1
Nathaniel Gan Fictionalism and Meinongianism
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Fictionalism about a kind of disputed object is often motivated by the fact that the view interprets discourse about those objects literally without an ontological commitment to them. This paper argues that this motivation is inadequate because some viable alternatives to fictionalism have similar attractions. Meinongianism—the view that there are true statements about non-existent objects—is one such view. Meinongianism bears significant similarity to fictionalism, so intuitive doubts about its viability are difficult to sustain for fictionalists. Moreover, Meinongianism avoids some of fictionalism’s weaknesses, thus it is even preferable to fictionalism in some respects.
79. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 36 > Issue: 1
Antonio Blanco Salgueiro Uptake: ¿entender o aceptar?
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Austin introduces the idea of securing the uptake in the context of dealing with the illocution-perlocution distinction. In recent times, the notion is employed by some neoaustinian scholars to argue that the uptake is what triggers the deontic effects (rights, duties, obligations, permissions, etc.) associated to an illocution. Here, a distinction is made between two kinds of uptake: uptake-as-understanding and uptake-asaccepting, and the stance that the second is the one needed for a plausible theory of speech action inspired by Austin’s original ideas is defended. When that notion is adopted, some old problems about speech action can be clarified.
80. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science: Volume > 36 > Issue: 1
Javier Suárez El holobionte/hologenoma como nivel de seleccion: una aproximacion a la evolucion de los consorcios de multiples especies
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
The units or levels of selection debate concerns the question of what kind of biological systems are stable enough that part of their evolution is a result of the process of natural selection acting at their level. Traditionally, the debate has concerned at least two different, though related, questions: the question of the level at which interaction with the environment occurs (which entity acts as an interactor), and the question of the level at which reproduction occurs (which entity acts as a replicator or reproducer). In recent years, biologists and philosophers have discussed a new aspect of this debate, namely the possibility that certain multi-species consortia formed by a host and its microbiome (holobionts/ hologenomes) may act as a unit of selection. This thesis, however, has not been without criticism, as it is doubtful that such consortia could meet the conditions required to achieve the degree of stability that would allow them to experience natural selection. The purpose of this paper is to systematically examine such criticisms and to defend the thesis that the holobiont/hologenome can act as a genuine level of selection both in the form of an interactor and in the form of a reproducer. To do so, it will be argued that the microbiome should be characterized in functional rather than taxonomic terms.