Cover of Thought: A Journal of Philosophy
Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Displaying: 21-37 of 37 documents


original articles
21. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 8 > Issue: 2
Sylvia Wenmackers Demystifying the Mystery Room
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
The Mystery Room problem is a close variant of the Mystery Bag scenario (due to Titelbaum). It is argued here that dealing with this problem requires no revision of the Bayesian formalism, since there exists a solution to this problem in which indexicals or demonstratives play no essential role. The solution does require labels, which are internal to the probabilistic model. While there needs to be a connection between at least one label and one indexical or demonstrative, that connection is external to the probabilistic model that is used to determine the relevant conditional probability; hence, it does not complicate the update procedure.
22. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 8 > Issue: 2
Blake Myers A Paradox Involving Representational States and Activities
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In this paper, I present a novel paradox that pertains to a variety of representational states and activities. I begin by proving that there are certain contingently true propositions that no one can occurrently believe.Then, I use this to develop a further proof by which I derive a contradiction, thus giving us the paradox. Next, I differentiate the paradox fromthe Liar Paradox, and I show how a common response to the different variations of the Liar Paradox fails to avoid the type of paradox provided in this paper. Finally, I demonstrate how the general ideas behind the paradox regarding occurrent belief can be extended to a wide range of other representational states and activities.
23. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 8 > Issue: 2
Vuko Andrić Hedonism, Desirability and the Incompleteness Objection
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Hedonism claims that all and only pleasure is intrinsically good. One worry about Hedonism focuses on the “only” part: Are there not things other than pleasure, such as personal projects and relationships, that are intrinsically good? If so, it can be objected that Hedonism is incomplete. In this paper, I defend Hedonism against this objection by arguing for a distinction between goodness and desirability that understands “desirability” as a deontic concept, in terms of “reason to desire”, but goodness as an evaluative concept. Based on this distinction, I attempt to show that Hedonists should accept that things other than pleasure, such as personal projects and relationships, are desirable for their own sakes but deny that these things are intrinsically good [Corrections added on 3 May 2019 after first online publication: The original abstract text is now the first paragraph of the paper’s introduction. An updated abstract has been added.]
24. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 8 > Issue: 2
Jaakko Hirvelä Knowing Without Having The Competence to Do So
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
According to all varieties of virtue reliabilism, knowledge is always gained through the exercise of epistemic competences.These competences can be conceived as competences to form true beliefs, or as competences to know. I will present a short but decisive argument against the idea that knowledge is always gained through the exercise of competences to know.The competence to know isn’t necessary for gaining knowledge.
25. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 8 > Issue: 2
Travis Timmerman, Bob Fischer The Problem with Person-Rearing Accounts of Moral Status
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Agnieszka Jaworska and Julie Tannenbaum recently developed the ingenious and novel person-rearing account of moral status, which preserves the commonsense judgment that humans have a higher moral status than nonhuman animals. It aims to vindicate speciesist judgments while avoiding the problems typically associated with speciesist views. We argue, however, that there is good reason to reject person-rearing views. Person-rearing views have to be coupled with an account of flourishing, which will (according to Jaworska and Tannenbaum) be either a species norm or an intrinsic potential account of flourishing. As we show, however, person-rearing accounts generate extremely implausible consequences when combined with the accounts of flourishing Jaworska and Tannenbaum need for the purposes of their view.
26. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 8 > Issue: 2
Alexander Gebharter, Dennis Graemer, Frenzis H. Scheffels Establishing Backward Causation on Empirical Grounds: An Interventionist Approach
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
We propose an analysis of backward causation in terms of interventionism that can avoid several problems typically associated with backward causation. Its main advantage over other accounts is that it allows for reducing the problematic task of supporting backward causal claims to the unproblematic task of finding evidence for several ordinary forward directed causal hypotheses.
27. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 8 > Issue: 2
Daniel Pallies Why Humean Causation Is Extrinsic
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
According to a view that goes by “Humeanism,” causal facts supervene on patterns of worldly entities.The simplest form of Humeanism is the constant conjunction theory: a particular type-F thing causes a particular type-G thing iff (i) that type-F is conjoined with that type-G thing and (ii) all F’s are conjoined with G’s. The constant conjunction theory implies that all causation is extrinsic, in the following sense: for all positive causal facts pertaining to each possible region, it’s extrinsic to that region that those causal facts pertain to it. Actual Humeans don’t accept the constant conjunction theory; they accept more sophisticated versions of Humeanism. But I argue that they, too, are committed to the thesis that all causation is extrinsic. In arguing for this claim, I use a discussion from Brian Weatherson as a springboard. Weatherson argues that on a plausible Humean view, some regions are such that all of their possible duplicates have the same or similar natural laws. I show that this is false. If Humeanism is true, then for every possible region, there are possible duplicates of that region with utterly alien natural laws. As a consequence, no causal facts pertain intrinsically to any region.
corrigendum
28. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 8 > Issue: 2
Proving that the Mind Is Not a Machine?
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
issue information
29. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 8 > Issue: 1
Issue Information
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
original articles
30. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 8 > Issue: 1
Oliver Tatton-Brown Primitive Recursion and Isaacson’s Thesis
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Although Peano arithmetic (PA) is necessarily incomplete, Isaacson argued that it is in a sense conceptually complete: proving a statement of the language of PA that is independent of PA will require conceptual resources beyond those needed to understand PA. This paper gives a test of Isaacon’s thesis. Understanding PA requires understanding the functions of addition and multiplication. It is argued that grasping these primitive recursive functions involves grasping the double ancestral, a generalized version of the ancestral operator. Thus, we can test Isaacon’s thesis by seeing whether when we phrase arithmetic in a context with the double ancestral operator, the result is conservative over PA. This is a stronger version of the test given by Smith, who argued that understanding the predicate “natural number” requires understanding the ancestral operator, but did not investigate what is required to understand the arithmetic functions.
31. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 8 > Issue: 1
Neil Sinhababu One-Person Moral Twin Earth Cases
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
This paper presents two cases demonstrating that theories allowing the environment to partially determine the content of moral concepts (such as the causal theory of reference) that provide incorrect truth-conditions for moral terms. While typical Moral Twin Earth cases seek to establish that these theories fail to account formoral disagreement, neither case here essentially involves interpersonal disagreement. Both involve a single person retaining moral beliefs despite recognizing actual or potential mismatches with the purportedly content-determining facts. This lets opponents of such theories grant objections that standard Moral Twin Earth cases fail to demonstrate disagreement, and argue more straightforwardly that they generate implausible truth-conditions for moral claims.
32. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 8 > Issue: 1
Henry Taylor Modal Combinatorialism is Consistent with S5
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
The combinatorial theory of modality has long been dogged by the supposed problem that it entails that S5 is not the correct logic for metaphysical modality. In this paper, I suggest a modification to combinatorialism, to eliminate this tension with S5. I argue that the resulting view is more in the spirit of combinatorialism than the original position.
33. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 8 > Issue: 1
Katherine Ritchie Should We Use Racial and Gender Generics?
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Recently several philosophers have argued that racial, gender, and other social generic generalizations should be avoided given their propensity to promote essentialist thinking, obscure the social nature of categories, and contribute to oppression. Here I argue that a general prohibition against social generics goes too far. Given that the truth of many generics require regularities or systematic rather than mere accidental correlations, they are our best means for describing structural forms of violence and discrimination. Moreover, their accuracy, their persistence in the face of counterexamples, and features of the contemporary socio-political context make generics useful linguistic tools in social justice projects.
34. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 8 > Issue: 1
Yale Weiss Are Contradictions Believable?
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
A number of philosophers deny that contradictions can be believed. Are they correct? In this note, I showthat even in quite weak logics, on pain of inconsistency, if there are false beliefs, either there are propositions which are true but unbelievable or contradictions are believable. Since the antecedent clearly holds, I offer some considerations in favor of the latter disjunct. Objections and variants of the main argument are considered.
35. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 8 > Issue: 1
Justin A. Capes What the Consequence Argument Is an Argument For
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
The consequence argument is among the most influential arguments for the conclusion that free will and determinism are incompatible. Recently, however, it has become increasingly clear that the argument fails to establish that particular incompatibilist conclusion. Even so, a version of the argument can be formulated that supports a different incompatibilist conclusion, according to which free will is incompatible with our behavior being predetermined by factors beyond our control. This conclusion, though not equivalent to the traditional incompatibilist thesis that determinism strictly precludes free will, is something many incompatibilists have had in mind all along and, indeed, is arguably the more central incompatibilist position. The consequence argument thus remains philosophically important, even if, as several of its critics have argued, it can’t be used to establish the strict incompatibility of free will and determinism.
36. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 8 > Issue: 1
Kai-Yee Wong, Chi-Ho Hung Trespassers and Existential Import
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
It is a received view of the post-Fregean predicate logic that a universal statement has no existential import and thus does not entail its particular (existential) counterpart. This paper takes issue with the view by discussing the trespasser case, which has widely been employed for supporting the view. The trespasser case in fact involves a shift of context. Properly understood, the case provides no support for the received view but rather suggests that we rethink the ‘quantity view’ of the existential import of quantifiers
37. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy: Volume > 8 > Issue: 1
Giulia Felappi The Face-Value Theory, Know-that, Know-wh and Know-how
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
For sentences such as "(1) Columbus knows that the sea is unpredictable" there is a face-value theory, according to which ‘that’-clauses are singular terms denoting propositions. Famously, Prior raised an objection to the theory, but defenders of the face-value theory such as Forbes, King, Künne, Pietroski and Stanley urged that the objection could bemet by maintaining that in (1) ‘to know’ designates a complex relation along the lines of being in a state of knowledge having as content. Is the theory safe, then? The aim of this paper is to show that a new problem for the theory arises if we consider some clauses other than ‘that’-clauses.