Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Browse by:



Displaying: 1-20 of 44 documents


articles
1. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 24 > Issue: 4
Merold Westphal The Importance of Mystery for the Life of Faith
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
That the life of Christian faith needs to understand itself as dwelling in the realm of mystery, of that which exceeds and overwhelms any languageand concepts with which we seek to understand it, is suggested at three sites in continental philosophy of religion: Heidegger’s critique of ontotheology,Marcel’s distinction between problems and mysteries, and Marion’s distinction between idol and icon, along with his account of the saturatedphenomenon. All three see the category of mystery as much wider than its religious usage but as crucial for a proper understanding and practice ofChristian faith.
2. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 24 > Issue: 4
Derek Malone-France LIBERALISM, FAITH, AND THE VIRTUE OF ‘ANXIETY’
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
I argue for a re-appropriation of the religious/philosophical concept of ‘anxiety’ regarding human finitude and fallibility as an ‘epistemic virtue’ thatshould frame the relationship between personal (including religious) belief and political participation and procedures. I contend that moral justificationsof liberal norms based on ‘respect for persons’ and ‘tolerance’ are insufficient without relation to such a (complementary) epistemic basis. Furthermore, Iargue that a careful examination of the internal logic of religious belief, per se, undermines traditional understandings of ‘faith’ (as being categoricallyopposed to ‘doubt’) and reveals support for liberal norms as an necessary implication thereof.
3. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 24 > Issue: 4
Eric Reitan A GUARANTEE OF UNIVERSAL SALVATION?
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Recent defenders of the Christian doctrine of eternal damnation have appealed to what I call the “No Guarantee Doctrine” (NG)—the doctrine that not evenGod can ensure both (a) that every person who is saved freely chooses to be saved and (b) that all are saved. Thomas Talbott challenges NG on the groundsthat anyone who is truly free will have no motive to reject God and will infallibly choose salvation. In response to critics of Talbott , I argue that in order toavoid Talbott ’s critique of NG, its defenders must adopt a view of human freedom in which there is a random element in choice. And if free choice involvessuch an element, then it is within God’s power to achieve a mathematical guarantee of freely chosen salvation for all. Thus, NG must be rejected.
4. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 24 > Issue: 4
Alexander R. Pruss PROPHECY WITHOUT MIDDLE KNOWLEDGE
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
While it might seem prima facie plausible that divine foreknowledge is all that is needed for prophecy, this seems incorrect. To issue a prophecy, God hasto know not just how someone will act, but how someone would act were the prophecy issued. This makes some think that Middle Knowledge is required.I argue that Thomas Flint’s two Middle Knowledge based accounts of prophecy are unsatisfactory, but one of them can be repaired. However the resources needed for repair also yield a sketch of a foreknowledge-only account of prophecy.
5. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 24 > Issue: 4
John Martin Fischer, Neal A. Tognazzini Exploring Evil and Philosophical Failure: A Critical Notice of Peter Van Inwagen's The Problem of Evil
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In his recent book on the problem of evil, Peter van Inwagen argues that both the global and local arguments from evil are failures. In this paper, we engagevan Inwagen’s book at two main points. First, we consider his understanding of what it takes for a philosophical argument to succeed. We argue that whilehis criterion for success is interesting and helpful, there is good reason to think it is too stringent. Second, we consider his responses to the global andlocal arguments from evil. We argue that although van Inwagen may have adequately responded to each of these arguments, his discussion points us toa third argument from evil to which he has yet to provide a response.
reviews
6. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 24 > Issue: 4
Timothy Chappell Jonathan Kvanvig: The Value of Knowledge and the Pursuit of Understanding
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
7. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 24 > Issue: 4
Sarah Borden Brian Davies and Brian Leftow: The Cambridge Companion to Anselm
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
8. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 24 > Issue: 4
John Kronen Richard Cross: Duns Scotus on God
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
9. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 24 > Issue: 4
Todd C. Ream, Thomas W. Seat II Jean-Pierre Torrell and Benedict M. Guevin: Aquinas’s Summa: Background, Structure, & Reception
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
articles
10. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 24 > Issue: 3
Thomas P. Flint FROM THE EDITOR
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
11. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 24 > Issue: 3
Peter King DAMAGED GOODS: HUMAN NATURE AND ORIGINAL SIN
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
The Doctrine of Original Sin seems to require that human nature has literally undergone a change from its prelapsarian to its postlapsarian condition.It is not clear that this claim makes sense. How can human nature, the feature(s) in virtue of which human beings are what they are, change in time? (Think of the parallel claim about √2.) I consider three medieval attempts to resolve this problem: (1) Augustine’s two theories about shared human nature; (2) Anselm’s proposal that original sin is an individual deficiency; (3) the “biological” proposal suggested by Odo of Cambrai and developed by Pseudo-Joscelin.
12. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 24 > Issue: 3
John T. Mullen CAN EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY CONFIRM ORIGINAL SIN?
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Christian responses to the developing field of evolutionary psychology tend to be defensive, focusing on the task of showing that Christians have not beenpresented with any reason to abandon any central beliefs of the Christian faith. A more positive response would seek to show that evolutionary psychologycan provide some sort of epistemic support for one or more distinctively Christian doctrines. This paper is an attempt to supply such a response by focusing on the distinctively Christian doctrine of original sin, which presents itself as an especially likely candidate for support from evolutionary psychology. I consider five versions of the doctrine in order of increasing content, arguing that all but the last can receive such support. However, in order to argue for the fourth version (which includes the doctrine traditionally described as “original guilt”), I enlist the aid of a Molinist understanding of divine providence. A consequence of this application of Molinism is that God holds us morally accountable, not only for what we actually do, but also for what we would do in any non-actual conditions, and that He acts on His knowledge of what we would do in such conditions. Because many may find this consequence problematic, I also argue that it is both morally acceptableand necessary for the perfection of the relationship between God and human beings. The last version of original sin that I consider insists that it must be thecausal product of the first sin of the first human being(s), but I argue that this is not a reasonable alternative if original sin is to be equated with behavioraltendencies inherited from an evolutionary ancestry.
13. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 24 > Issue: 3
Kevin Timpe Grace and Controlling What We Do Not Cause
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Eleonore Stump has recently articulated an account of grace which is neither deterministic nor Pelagian. Drawing on resources from Aquinas’s moral psychology, Stump’s account of grace affords the quiescence of the will a significant role in an individual’s coming to saving faith. In the present paper, I firstoutline Stump’s account and then raise a worry for that account. I conclude by suggesting a metaphysic that provides a way of resolving this worry. The resulting view allows one to maintain both (i) that divine grace is the efficient cause of saving faith and (ii) that humans control whether or not they come to saving faith.
14. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 24 > Issue: 3
Katherin A. Rogers GOD IS NOT THE AUTHOR OF SIN: AN ANSELMIAN RESPONSE TO MCCANN
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Following Anselm of Canterbury I argue against Hugh McCann’s claim that a traditional, classical theist understanding of God’s relationship to creation entails that God is the cause of our choices, including our choice to sin. I explain Anselm’s thesis that God causes all that has ontological status, yet does not cause sin. Then I show that McCann’s God, if not a sinner, must nonetheless be an unloving deceiver, McCann’s theodicy fails on its own terms, his proposed requirements for moral authenticity are insufficient, and his suggestion that his universe is “safer” than Anselm’s is misguided.
15. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 24 > Issue: 3
Justin D. Barnard PURGATORY AND THE DILEMMA OF SANCTIFICATION
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Christian Protestants typically affirm both the essential moral perfection of heaven and the sufficiency of saving faith. Yet these two commitments generatean apparently self-destructive dilemma—one I call the dilemma of sanctification. The prima facie puzzle can be resolved in at least three ways. In this paper, I articulate the dilemma of sanctification in some detail and offer an argument against a widely-held Protestant solution I call provisionism. This constitutes indirect support for the solution I find most promising, namely, a doctrine of purgatory. I close by sketching a model of purgatory consistent with Protestant soteriology.
16. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 24 > Issue: 3
David Vander Laan THE SANCTIFICATION ARGUMENT FOR PURGATORY
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
A recently advanced argument for purgatory hinges on the need for complete sanctification before one can enter heaven. The argument has a modal gap.The gap can be exploited to fashion a competing account of how sanctification occurs in the afterlife according to which it is in part a heavenly process.The competing account usefully complicates the overall case for purgatory and raises questions about how the notion ought to be understood.
reviews
17. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 24 > Issue: 3
Mark D. Linville J. L. Schellenberg: Prolegomena to a Philosophy of Religion
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
18. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 24 > Issue: 3
Kelly James Clark Joel B. Green and Stuart L. Palmer: In Search of the Soul
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
19. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 24 > Issue: 3
Joseph Jedwab Phil Dowe: Galileo, Darwin, and Hawking: The Interplay of Science, Reason, and Religion
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
20. Faith and Philosophy: Volume > 24 > Issue: 3
Andrew Dole John Cottingham: The Spiritual Dimension: Religion, Philosophy and Human Value
view |  rights & permissions | cited by