Cover of Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association
Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Displaying: 1-20 of 2560 documents


contributed papers
1. Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association: Volume > 95
Daniel Shields Infinite Regress and the Hume-Edwards-Ockham Objection: A Thomistic Analysis
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
One of the standard objections against the impossibility of infinite regress is associated with David Hume and Paul Edwards, but originates with William Ockham. They claim that in an infinite regress every member of the series is explained, and nothing is unexplained. Every member is explained by the one before it, and the series as a whole is nothing over and above its members, and so needs no cause of its own. Utilizing the well-known Thomistic distinction between essentially ordered and accidentally ordered causal series, I show that the Hume-Edwards-Ockham objection fails to touch Aquinas’s argument against the impossibility of infinite regress in an essentially ordered series. However, Aquinas also argues that accidentally ordered causal series can only regress infinitely if supported by an everlasting essential cause. The Hume-Edwards-Ockham objection does raise a question about this thesis, but I show how St. Thomas can reply to it convincingly.
2. Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association: Volume > 95
Patrick Fisher The Metaphysics of Mathematical Explanation in Science: Platonist and Nominalist Problems and Aristotelian Solutions
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Debates between contemporary platonist and nominalist conceptions of the metaphysical status of mathematical objects have recently included discussions of explanations of physical phenomena in which mathematics plays an indispensable role, termed mathematical explanations in science (MES). I will argue that MES requires an ontology that can (1) ground claims about mathematical necessity as distinct from physical necessity and (2) explain how that mathematical necessity applies to the physical world. I contend that nominalism fails to meet the first criterion and platonism the second. I then articulate an alternative, Aristotelian approach to mathematical objects and defend such a view as meeting both criteria.
3. Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association: Volume > 95
Daniel Patrick Moloney Moralistic Therapeutic Holiness: A Catholic Defense of Philosophy as Therapy for the Soul
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Christian Smith has described the religious attitudes of American youth and many adults as Moralistic Therapeutic Deism. In this formulation the word “therapeutic” does much work, and is meant to indicate that the goal of life is to be happy, to which end religion is instrumental. Martha Nussbaum has argued that Hellenistic schools of philosophy were therapeutic and instrumental in much the same way, and that this is a possible mode of philosophy even today. Appealing to the historical investigations of Pierre Hadot and Giovanni Reale, this paper shows that Neoplatonism was an even more successful form of therapeutic philosophy, a fact which Augustine recognized and to which he responded in his therapeutic masterpiece Confessions, through his depiction of his mother as a sage. This suggests that Catholicism can be powerful when presented therapeutically, which might be a more appropriate mode for evangelism in our therapeutic age.
4. Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association: Volume > 95
Marie George, Marie George Is Nicanor Austriaco’s Reformulation of Hylomorphism in Terms of Systems Biology Successful?
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
The systems perspective, as applied to biology, involves regarding organisms as systems consisting of biological molecules in motion; its goal is to determine which interacting molecules make up the organism and how their interactions change over time. I argue here that Nicanor Austriaco’s attempt at reformulating Aristotelian-Thomistic hylomorphism in terms of the systems perspective fails because it looks to systems biology to answer questions that only natural philosophy can answer. These questions include whether an organism is collection of parts having accidental unity or is a substance, what constitutes an emergent property, and what role the final cause plays in understanding organisms. In addition, insufficient attention is paid to the Aristotelian-Thomistic tenet that the soul can only be united to a suitably disposed body, namely, one with organs. Nothing is offered to show that this tenet can be accorded with a perspective that views organisms as networks of interacting molecules.
5. Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association: Volume > 95
John Skalko Aquinas on Animal Cognitive Action in Light of the Texts of Aristotle
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Aquinas famously held that only intellectual beings can grasp the natures or essences of things and cognize universals per se. Below these intellectual beings, however, were the non-human animals who shared many of the interior sense faculties in common with man; such animals’ highest sense was merely what is called the estimative power. Aquinas’s account of animal cognition has largely been ignored in contemporary biological research, although hopes for a resurgence have been emerging in the Thomistic world. In this paper I seek to explicate Aquinas’s account of animal cognitive activities, particularly by explicating a more detailed account of animal cognitive action as found in the biological works of Aristotle known by Aquinas. I then turn to various contemporary biological findings to show that many purported modern discoveries (like dolphins rescuing a man or recognition of social hierarchies) shouldn’t be so surprising after all. Many such cognitive acts were already there in the texts of Aristotle read by Aquinas.
6. Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association: Volume > 95
William Hannegan The Problem of Enframing for Natural Law
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Understanding traditional natural law requires us to understand the concept of intrinsic nature, as well related concepts such as intrinsic inclination to an end and nature fulfillment. In this paper, I argue that proponents of traditional natural law theory should be attentive to the work of Martin Heidegger. If Heidegger is right about what he says concerning modern technology, then modern technology poses a threat to our understanding of the concept of intrinsic human nature and other associated concepts, and thus a threat to our understanding of natural law. Heidegger may also provide an insight into how proponents of traditional natural law can respond to the threat of modern technology. Advocates of traditional natural law theory can respond to the threat of modern technology by engaging in, and promoting, certain arts, trades, skills, and activities that reveal natures. I show that farming is a paradigmatic example.
7. Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association: Volume > 95
Harrison Lee Four Objections to a Broad Scope Theory of Intention
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Proponents of “broad scope” theories of intention argue that agents cannot intend to achieve given ends without intending certain inevitable or probable consequences. I shall argue that some Thomistic variants of these theories collapse into the Expectation View (EV), i.e., that we intend to produce all of the consequences that we expect to result from our actions. I shall then raise four objections to EV. First, EV falsely implies that we intend to produce all of the expected beneficial consequences of our actions. Second, EV falsely renders altruistic self-sacrifice a species of suicide. Third, EV falsely implies that medical interventions with probable fatalities must involve intentional killing even when, of the available options, they offer the most likely prospects of long-term survival. Fourth, EV falsely implies that foreseeably fatal actions must involve intentional killing even when they will foreseeably prolong the agent’s life before killing him.
8. Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association: Volume > 95
Marial Corona Philosophy as Teacher and Pupil: Wisdom from Two Nineteenth-Century Philosophers
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
If philosophy is to be faithful to her calling to serve truth and humankind, she must remain a pupil, open to the enrichment that other sciences bestow on her. This paper highlights some insights from J. H. Newman and C. S. Peirce that can shed light on our understanding of philosophy as a servant to the truth. Newman and Peirce are suitable guides for this discussion since both cultivated their intellect in various disciplines, which informed their philosophical contributions. It begins by exploring how Newman and Peirce conceived philosophy as a science. Then, it discusses their views on the unity of science, which further qualify their thoughts on philosophy. Finally, it enounces some consequences for the study of philosophy which their contributions suggest. Among many others, Newman and Peirce stand out as courageous defenders of the truth and have much to contribute to the timeless conversation of philosophy.
9. Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association: Volume > 95
Francis Feingold Reasons of the Heart: The “Evidence” of Love in Pascal’s Pensées
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Pascal, in his Pensées, applies philosophy to a theological problem: reconciling (a) Christianity’s demand for absolute faith with both (b) the motives of credibility’s inability to justify absolute faith on their own and (c) the moral obligation to avoid superstition. This reconciliation hinges upon distinguishing two cognitive faculties: reason, and the heart. I will first discuss Pascal’s view of the difference between reason and the heart, and specifically how they each relate to evidence and certainty: reason discursively and probabilistically, the heart holistically and with certitude. Then I turn to Pascal’s view of the role which the heart plays in religious faith, and apply this view to the problem of basing absolute assent on limited evidence. Finally, I will examine Pascal’s view of reason’s important supporting role in faith, and apply it to the obligation to avoid superstitious belief
acpa report and minutes
10. Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association: Volume > 95
Minutes of the 2021 Executive Council Meeting
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
11. Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association: Volume > 95
American Catholic Philosophical Association Secretary’s Report (2021)
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
12. Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association: Volume > 95
American Catholic Philosophical Association Treasurer’s Report (2020)
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
presidential address
13. Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association: Volume > 94
Thomas A. Cavanaugh Capax Veritatis: Against Student-Commodification
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
presentation of the aquinas medal
14. Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association: Volume > 94
Angela Knobel Presentation of the Aquinas Medal
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
plenary sessions
15. Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association: Volume > 94
John Haldane Beauty before Aesthetics, and Aesthetics after Beauty
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
16. Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association: Volume > 94
Katherine Rogers Anselm on Truth and Truth-telling
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
contributed papers
17. Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association: Volume > 94
Joseph Cherny A Defense of Robert Nozick’s Theory of the Meaning of Life: Some Thomistic Considerations
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Robert Nozick argues that the problem of the meaning of life is caused by limitations, especially death. Consequently, attaining meaning in one’s life requires connecting to something larger than oneself. Since anything can be conceived of as meaningless from a wide enough perspective, meaning will ultimately depend on connecting to “the unlimited.” Although initially plausible, this theory of meaning is vulnerable to a number of objections. One is that “the unlimited” is an incoherent notion due to the necessity that it include ideas that are contradictory to each other, and another is that the meaning of life ought to include internal goods, which Nozick ignores. I will defend Nozick’s theory against these two objections by bringing in elements of the thought of Aristotle and St. Thomas.
18. Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association: Volume > 94
Chad Engelland Three Versions of the Question, “Why Is There Something Rather than Nothing?”
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In dialogue with Stephen Hawking, Martin Heidegger, and Thomas Aquinas, I argue that there are three different and compatible ways to understand the question, “Why is there something rather than nothing?” (1) The scientific way asks about the origin of the cosmos. (2) The transcendental way asks about the origin of experience. (3) The metaphysical way asks about the origin of existence. The questions work independent of each other, so that answering one version of the question does not affect the other two versions. Hawking and Heidegger are therefore mistaken to think that the scientific and transcendental questions render otiose the metaphysical question concerning the origin of existence.
19. Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association: Volume > 94
Pol Vandevelde The Romantic Hermeneutic Ideal of “Understanding Better” as an Ethical Imperative
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
I argue that the romantic notion of “understanding better,” as the ideal of interpretation according to Schleiermacher and Schlegel, is not a “meliorative” understanding, retrospectively situating the work in a broader conceptual or historical context and thus surpassing what the original author meant. The qualification “better” is ethical insofar as it indicates a future-oriented task of responding for the authors and contributing to the continued life of their work. What guides interpreters in such an ethical task is benevolence or love, both toward the object of interpretation—the work—and the author of the work. Love is a hermeneutic imperative that has two sides: first, interpretation “augments” the work or brings it to its “second power;” and, second, interpreters need to put themselves in a certain attitude of non-understanding so that the work will not be constricted in pre-established categories and, instead, susceptible to challenge interpreters.
20. Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association: Volume > 94
Traci Phillipson Averroes’s Tahafut al-Tahafut, The Third Discussion: A Methodological Approach to Truth
view |  rights & permissions | cited by