Cover of American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly
Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Displaying: 1-20 of 1742 documents


2022 rising scholar essay contest
1. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 97 > Issue: 3
Christopher W. Love Virtue and the Paradox of Tragedy
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
What accounts for our pleasure in tragic art? In a widely-cited essay, Susan Feagin argues that this pleasure has moral roots; it arises when we discover ourselves to be the sort of people who respond sympathetically to another’s suffering. Although critical of Feagin’s particular solution to the tragedy paradox, I too believe that our pleasure in tragedy often has moral roots. I trace those roots differently, however, by placing the concept of virtue front and center. I argue that a noble pleasure arises when we perceive virtue in tragic characters and when we practice it ourselves as audience members. My account draws on insights from the history of philosophy, most notably Aquinas’s conception of the virtues of charity and mercy in the Summa.
articles
2. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 97 > Issue: 3
Michael Szlachta Unde huic fictioni non est respondendum: Thomas Aquinas and the Necessitation of the Will
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
William de la Mare suggests in his Correctorium fratris Thomae that it is possible to read Aquinas as saying that the will is necessitated by the intellect. Early defenders of Aquinas thought that this was nonsense (a fictio). However, I analyze Aquinas’s corpus and show that he has a consistent view of the relationship between the will and the intellect according to which the will is indeed necessitated by the intellect, not absolutely but conditionally: it is necessary that, if the intellect apprehends some object as good, then the will wills that object. However, I also argue that, although Aquinas is committed to the necessitation of the will by the intellect, it does not follow that the will lacks alternate possibilities.
3. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 97 > Issue: 3
Kateřina Kutarňová Philip of the Blessed Trinity on Mystical Knowledge: Peculiar Kinds of Species
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
This study concerns the theory of mystical knowledge advanced by the practically unknown seventeenth-century Carmelite author Philip of the Blessed Trinity in his work Summa Theologiae Mysticae. Philip introduces “a new kind” of spiritual species representing the intellectibilia to describe how individuals are granted mystical knowledge, and in doing so distinguishes between three kinds of species. Philip’s notion of mystical knowledge is closely related to the topic of contemplation and is profoundly influenced by The Interior Castle of St. Teresa of Avila. The analysis presented here, therefore, represents an original contribution to the ongoing scholarly study of species, (mystical) knowledge, and Teresian spirituality.
4. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 97 > Issue: 3
Matthew Shea Value Incommensurability in Natural Law Ethics: A Clarification and Critique
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
The foundation of natural law ethics is a set of basic human goods, such as life and health, knowledge, work and play, appreciation of beauty, friendship, and religion. A disputed question among natural law theorists is whether the basic goods are “incommensurable.” But there is widespread ambiguity in the natural law literature about what incommensurability means, which makes it unclear how this disagreement should be understood and resolved. First, I clear up this ambiguity by distinguishing between incommensurability and incomparability. I show that proponents of New Natural Law Theory hold that basic goods are both incommensurable and incomparable, whereas proponents of Classical Natural Law Theory hold that basic goods are incommensurable but comparable. Second, I critique the leading New Natural Law arguments for the incomparability of basic goods. Throughout the article, I explain why value incommensurability is an essential feature of natural law ethics but value incomparability is not.
5. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 97 > Issue: 3
Daniel Schwartz Suárez’s Republic of Demons: Could There Be an Obligation to Do Evil?
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Suárez was probably the first theologian to propose a political understanding of the order of subordination among the demons. According to Aquinas, this subordination immediately reflects the natural differences in perfection between the demons. Suárez charged that a natural-based order of demonic subordination could not ground the capacity of the demons’ ruler—Lucifer—to use his power to impose civic obligations on fellow demons so as to pursue their joint evil goals. But can there be obligations ad malum? This paper explores a number of possible paths seemingly available to Suárez to defend his controversial view. I argue that the most promising interpretation of Suárez is one according to which the obligations created by Lucifer’s commands are not obligations in conscience but rather what we may call “non-moral obligations.”
book review
6. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 97 > Issue: 3
Thomas M. Osborne, Jr. Conscience: Four Thomistic Treatments
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
7. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 97 > Issue: 3
Heidi M. Giebel The Way of Medicine: Ethics and the Healing Profession
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
8. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 97 > Issue: 3
Anthony J. Scordino By Way of Obstacles: A Pathway Through a Work
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
9. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 97 > Issue: 3
John J. Conley What Happened to Civility: The Promise and Failure of Montaigne's Modern Project
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
10. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 97 > Issue: 3
John F. Crosby The Two Greatest Ideas: How Our Grasp of the Universe and of Our Minds Changed Everything
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
introduction
11. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 97 > Issue: 2
Jack Zupko Introduction
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
articles
12. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 97 > Issue: 2
Chiara Beneduce John Buridan: The Human Body at the Intersection of Natural Philosophy and Medicine
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
This article considers the relationship between John Buridan’s natural philosophy and medicine. By examining some aspects of Buridan’s description of the human body related to sensation, nutrition, and generation—especially as they were framed in the so-called “controversy between philosophers and physicians”—this article shows that, though mostly faithful to Aristotelian doctrine, Buridan’s theoretical biology relies to a large extent on medical ideas.
13. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 97 > Issue: 2
Joël Biard John Buridan on the Question of the Unity of the Human Being
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Is a human being something that is one per se, or are humans composed of two independent substances? Treating the soul as the form of an organic body seems to offer one way of addressing the difficulty. But the debates about the nature of the soul which began to emerge in the 1270s made this question problematic. This article considers Buridan’s solution to the problem of how to unify what is corporeal and divisible on the one hand with what is incorporeal and indivisible on the other. Beginning with sensation, which concerns the unity of the sensitive soul and sense data, we turn to the act of thinking, where the intellective soul is united with the image or phantasm qua mover, leading to the realization that the unity of a human being is no longer self-evident. To solve the problem, Buridan takes up and transforms ways of thinking about the human soul inherited from older debates around Averroist psychology, such as the theory of two subjects and the conjunction of the sensible with the intelligible during cognitive activity.
14. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 97 > Issue: 2
Henrik Lagerlund Buridan’s Radical View of Final Causality and Its Influence
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In his commentary on Aristotle’s Physics, John Buridan (c. 1300–1361) presents his well-known rejection of final causality. The main problem he sees with it is that it requires the cause to exist before the effect. Despite this, he retains the terminology of ends. This has led to some difficulty interpreting Buridan’s view. In this article, I argue that one should not misunderstand Buridan’s terminology and think that he still retains some use or explanatory function for final causality in nature. To make this point, I look first at Buridan’s text, but then also at three thinkers who discuss Buridan’s view in detail: Albert of Saxony (d. 1390), Paul of Venice (d. 1429), and Luis Coronel (d. 1531). They all have a very clear idea of what Buridan’s view was and understand that it entails a rejection of final causality, but they also all preserve his distinctive terminology. Paul of Venice especially discusses and criticizes Buridan’s view in detail. Besides confirming my interpretation of the rejection of final causality, this study also shows that the view was extremely influential well into the sixteenth century and attributed to Buridan throughout two centuries.
15. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 97 > Issue: 2
Peter John Hartman Mirecourt, Mental Modes, and Mental Motions
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
What is an occurrent mental state? According to a common scholastic answer such a state is at least in part a quality of the mind. When I newly think about a machiatto, say, my mind acquires a new quality. However, according to a view discussed by John Buridan (who rejects it) and John of Mirecourt (who is condemned in 1347 for considering it “plausible”), an occurrent mental state is not even in part a quality. After sketching some of the history of this position, I will present two common arguments against it—the argument from change and the argument from agency. I will then turn to Mirecourt’s own position on the matter. Mirecourt, I show, in fact offers us two different theories about occurrent mental states. The first, which I call the conservation theory, accepts that mental states are in part qualities. However, a mental state is a quality together with an action on the side of the mind, namely, its conservation of a quality within itself. The second position, which I will call the pure-action theory, holds that an occurrent mental state is not even in part a quality; instead, it is an action the mind performs which is neither the production nor the conservation of a quality within itself. Mirecourt characterizes such pure actions as “modes” of the mind, and it is this position which is condemned in 1347. In the final section, I turn to an objection that both Buridan and Mirecourt raise against the pure-action theory: if accidental states of the mind are mere modes of the mind, then why not suppose that all accidents are mere modes of the subjects which they qualify?
16. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 97 > Issue: 2
Peter G. Sobol The Use of Theological Terms in the De anima Commentaries of Nicole Oresme and John Buridan
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Historian of science Edward Grant believed that, by counting and classifying the uses of theological terms in commentaries on some of Aristotle’s natural books, he could show that medieval natural philosophy had no theological agenda. But his broad-brush approach may not reveal differences in the way individual authors used theological terms. A census of such terms in the De anima commentaries of John Buridan and Nicole Oresme undertaken in this paper suggests that Buridan was more mindful of theological scrutiny of the Arts faculty than Oresme, perhaps because Buridan’s career began when the effects of the Condemnation of 1277 were more strongly felt than they were a generation later when Oresme began to teach.
17. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 97 > Issue: 1
Benjamin Robert Koons Warranted Catholic Belief
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Extending Alvin Plantinga’s model of warranted belief to the beliefs of groups as a whole, I argue that if the dogmatic beliefs of the Catholic Church are true, they are also warranted. Catholic dogmas are warranted because they meet the three conditions of my model: they are formed (1) by ministers functioning properly (2) in accordance with a design plan that is oriented towards truth and reliable (3) in a social environment sufficiently similar to that for which they were designed. I show that according to Catholic doctrine the authoritative spokespersons of the Church—ecumenical councils and popes—meet these conditions when defining dogmas. I also respond to the objection that the warrant of Catholic dogmas is defeated by the plurality of non-Catholic Christian sects that deny Catholic dogmas.
18. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 97 > Issue: 1
Logan Paul Gage, Frederick D. Aquino Newman the Fallibilist
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
The role of certitude in our mental lives is, to put it mildly, controversial. Many current epistemologists (including epistemologists of religion) eschew certitude altogether. Given his emphasis on certitude, some have maintained that John Henry Newman was an infallibilist about knowledge. In this paper, we argue that a careful examination of his thought (especially as seen in the Grammar of Assent) reveals that he was an epistemic fallibilist. We first clarify what we mean by fallibilism and infallibilism. Second, we explain why some have read Newman as an infallibilist. Third, we offer two arguments that Newman is at least a fallibilist in a weak sense. In particular, the paradox he seeks to resolve in the Grammar and his dispute with John Locke both indicate that he is at least a weak fallibilist. We close with a consideration of whether Newman is a fallibilist in a much stronger sense as well.
19. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 97 > Issue: 1
Hikmet Unlu A Transcategorial Conception of Dynamis and Energeia
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
On the standard interpretation of Metaphysics IX, Aristotle proceeds from the original sense of δύναμις and ἐνέργεια to an ontological conception of these terms. This should raise the question of what is not ontological about the former and what is ontological about the latter. To address these questions I discuss the commentaries by Heidegger and Menn, which alone come close to addressing these issues. But their readings cannot neatly distinguish between the two senses of δύναμις and ἐνέργεια that we find in the Aristotelian text, thus compelling us to seek a better way of clarifying the standard interpretation, which I argue can be more precisely understood in the following way: δύναμις and ἐνέργεια in their customary meaning cannot be considered ontological in the sense that they have a particular locus among the categories, which is what sets them apart from their newer, ontological meaning. I conclude therefore that the text of Metaphysics IX can be understood as proceeding from an intracategorial conception of δύναμις and ἐνέργεια toward a transcategorial conception of these terms.
20. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 97 > Issue: 1
Stefaan E. Cuypers A Correction to Dillard’s Reading of Geach’s Temporality Argument for Non-Materialism
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In his article “What Do We Think With?” Peter Geach develops an argument for the non-materiality of thinking. Given that basic thinking activity is not clockable in physical time, whereas basic material or bodily activity is so clockable, it follows that basic thinking activity is non-material. Peter Dillard’s attack on this temporality proof takes “thoughts” in the proof to refer to non-occurrent states. The present note shows this reading to be mistaken and so rectifies a misunderstanding of Geach’s argument. It takes no stand on the question of whether the argument succeeds.