Cover of Ancient Philosophy
Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Browse by:



Displaying: 1-20 of 1984 documents


articles
1. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 44 > Issue: 1
Nevim Borçin On the Alleged Epitome of Dialectic: Nicomachean Ethics vii 1.1145b2-7
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
A methodological statement that occurs at Nicomachean Ethics vii 1 and its implementation in the subsequent discussion has widely been called as ‘the method of endoxa’. According to a standard interpretation the method of endoxa follows some strict steps and is the paradigm of the dialectical method. I question this interpretation and argue for a deflationary and non-dialectical account which, I believe, conforms with Aristotle’s scientifically oriented general methodological program.
2. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 44 > Issue: 1
Andree Hahmann Cicero on Natural and Artificial Divination
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Cicero distinguishes between two forms of divination: natural and artificial divination. Most contemporary scholars assume that Cicero presents a Stoic division and some even draw far-reaching conclusions about the scientific status of divination based on this distinction. However, his justification for the division is apparently contradictory and neither fits with Stoic nor Peripatetic claims that are found elsewhere. This paper examines the exact meaning of the division and sheds light on its Stoic and Peripatetic origin. In this way, we will not only be able to better understand the overall argument of Cicero’s De divinatione, but also to assess his real achievement as a philosophical author.
reviews
3. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 44 > Issue: 1
William Prior Plato of Athens: A Life in Philosophy. By Robin Waterfield
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
4. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 44 > Issue: 1
Doug Al-Maini Plato’s Phaedo: Forms, Death, and the Philosophical Life. By David Ebrey
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
5. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 44 > Issue: 1
Douglas R. Campbell Cosmos and Perception in Plato’s Timaeus: In the Eye of the Cognitive Storm. By Mark Eli Kalderon
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
6. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 44 > Issue: 1
Lewis Meek Trelawny-Cassity Traditional and Cosmic Gods in Later Plato and the Early Academy. By Vilius Bartninkas
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
7. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 44 > Issue: 1
Shane Drefcinski Aristotle’s Discovery of the Human: Piety and Politics in the Nico­machean Ethics. By Mary P. Nichols
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
8. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 44 > Issue: 1
Vanessa de Harven Later Stoicism 155 BC to AD 200: An Introduction and Collection of Sources in Translation. By Brad Inwood
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
9. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 44 > Issue: 1
Lloyd P. Gerson Ontology in Early Neoplatonism. Plotinus, Porphyry, Iamblichus. By Riccardo Chiaradonna
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
articles
10. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 43 > Issue: 2
Marco Montagnino How Can Parmenides’ τὸ ἐόν Be Unending but Non-endless?
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
I walk a well-trodden but still only partially explored path, along which we shall attempt to establish a basis for the study of the Parmenides poem’s unity by way of a comparison with twentieth-century physics. I investigate the hypothesis that Parmenides’ sphere-shaped τὸ ἐόν, as described in B8.42-49, could be understood as a hyperspherical unlimited whole cosmologically bounded by the διάκοσμος described by the complex sphere system in fragment B12.
11. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 43 > Issue: 2
Radim Kočandrle Origins of the Spherical Earth in Ancient Greek Cosmology
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Diogenes Laertius ascribes the first concept of spherical Earth to both Pythagoras and Parmenides. Indeed, a major shift in cosmologies—emergence of the spherical conception of the Earth and the surrounding heaven—took place between the sixth and fifth centuries BCE. Given the poor state of preservation of early Pythagorean tradition, it is argued that primacy in formulating the notion of spherical Earth should be ascribed to Parmenides.
12. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 43 > Issue: 2
Matthew Matherne The Value of Socratic Inquiry in the Apology
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
What makes Socratic inquiry valuable? A standard response is what I term instrumentalism: Socratic inquiry is merely instrumentally valuable; it is valuable only because it produces valuable results. This paper challenges instrumentalism. First, I present two value puzzles for instrumentalists and argue that these puzzles are best solved by denying instrumentalism. Then, I survey passages in the Apology that point to the source of Socratic inquiry’s non-instrumental value.
13. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 43 > Issue: 2
Travis Mulroy Lucid Dreaming: On the Phantom of Justice in Plato’s Republic
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Near the end of Plato’s Republic iv, Socrates reveals that the justice discovered externally in the city is a phantom of justice, as opposed to the justice discovered internally in the individual, which is justice in truth (443b7-444a2). This paper explains the distinction between true justice and its phantom, as well as the significance of this distinction to the underlying argument of Plato’s Republic.
14. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 43 > Issue: 2
Richard D. Parry Deceptive Pleasures in Republic ix: Virtue’s Link with Philosophical Knowledge
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In Republic ix, Socrates begins his argument that deceptive pleasure causes insatiable desire by citing the error that cessation of pain is the greatest pleasure. Some interpret this error as an illusion, experiencing pleasure when there is no pleasure; but illusion cannot explain insatiable desire. Our interpretation explains insatiable desire—and Socrates’ restatement of wisdom and justice to include pleasures, which links the knowledge of unchanging reality with these virtues.
15. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 43 > Issue: 2
Ryan M. Brown The Thematic Significance of the Scenery in Plato’s Phaedrus
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In this essay, I discuss the philosophical significance of three features of the Phaedrus’s dramatic scenery: the myth of Boreas, the two trees Socrates singles out upon arriving at the grove, and the grove itself. I argue that attention to these three features of the dramatic scenery helps us better understand the Phaedrus’s account of erōs.
16. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 43 > Issue: 2
Denis Walter Definitional Structure and the Same, the Different, and Part-Whole Relations in Plato’s Parmenides
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
This article argues that the second part of the Parmenides (137-166) consists not only of the well-known logical structure that has been widely studied but also of a great variety of definitions of forms. My aim is to show how these definitions depend on a specific group of closely connected primary forms (i.e., same, different, part, whole). The definitions that Parmenides provides help Socrates overcome his failure in attempting to define forms in the first part of the dialogue.
17. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 43 > Issue: 2
Hermann Weidemann Aristotle on Bivalence and Truth-value Distribution: De interpretatione 9.18a34- b5
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
The passage 18a34-⁠b5 of Aristotle’s famous sea-battle chapter has often been misunderstood. My aim is to show, firstly, that Aristotle in this passage attempts to prove that the unrestricted validity of the Principle of Bivalence entails, in the case of singular statements, the validity of the Principle of Truth-value Distribution for the contradictory pairs they are members of. According to the latter principle either the affirmative member of a contradictory pair of statements must be true and the negative false or vice versa. Secondly, I want to show what consequences the correct understanding of the passage in question has for the understanding of the introductory passage of the chapter (18a28-⁠33) and for the dispute over whether Aristotle exempts singular statements about contingent future events from the domain of the Principle of Bivalence. The thesis, advanced by some modern interpreters, that Aristotle refrains from doing so even though he exempts the contradictory pairs such statements are members of from the domain of the Principle of Truth-value Distribution will be rebutted as resulting from a fallacious line of reasoning.
18. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 43 > Issue: 2
Andrea Libero Carbone The Logic of Consequence in Aristotle’s Biology
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Two of Aristotle’s major legacies, namely, the theory of scientific syllogism and teleology seem to conflict on several planes. Indeed, an array of formal limitations prevents him from formalizing teleological explanations into scientific syllogisms, which are entirely absent from his works. To achieve this, Aristotle resorts to a different tool, the logic of ‘consequence’. This governs both the teleological relation between an end and a means that underlies necessity ‘from a hypothesis’—which is the necessity proper to living things—and a different form of syllogisms, namely, syllogisms ‘from a hypothesis’. His guidelines in the first chapter of his Parts of Animals on the proper form of demonstration to be adopted in biology should be read as laying out the rules of inference for translating teleological explanations into syllogisms ‘from a hypothesis’.
19. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 43 > Issue: 2
Paul Asman Εὐθύς and Action in Aristotle’s Practical Syllogism
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Aristotle says that conclusions of practical syllogisms are actions that occur εὐθύς, which is normally translated to indicate temporal immediacy. Both aspects of this—that the conclusions are actions, and that they occur immediately—seem wrong. Interpreting εὐθύς as atemporal, specifically as indicating that nothing more is needed to explain the action, makes better sense of practical syllogisms and solves the problems raised by calling their conclusions actions.
20. Ancient Philosophy: Volume > 43 > Issue: 2
Brian Ribeiro Skeptic-cum-Augur: Was Cicero a Skeptical Fideist?
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In section 1 I present a case for understanding Cicero as a radical Academic skeptic, based on evidence from the Academica. In section 2 I offer an explanation of the concept of skeptical fideism and present a way to taxonomize various versions of the view. The material in sections 1 and 2 positions us to ask, was Cicero, the Academic augur, a sincere orthopraxic skeptical fideist? In section 3 I attempt to answer that question, beginning with an examination of De divinatione. Reading that work in a skeptical light, as I do, we are led to an impasse on our central question. However, in section 4 I consider two lines of argument that might enable us to determine Cicero’s own views.