Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Browse by:



Displaying: 21-40 of 50 documents


comment
21. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 23 > Issue: 3
David Abram A Reply to “Phenomenology versus Pragmatism”
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
news and notes
22. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 23 > Issue: 2
NEWS AND NOTES
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
features
23. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 23 > Issue: 2
Robert Briggs Wild Thoughts: A Deconstructive Environmental Ethics
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Although environmental ethics has become more familiar and comfortable with the work of postmodernism, “deconstruction” in particular continues to be depicted as “destructive” and “nihilistic.” A close examination of some specific works of deconstruction, however, shows that, far from denying responsibilities to the environment, deconstruction seeks to affirm a radical obligation toward the “other.” Because this possibility is habitually ruled out by denunciations of deconstruction’s imputed relativism, I begin with a dramatized account of the possible reception of deconstruction within environmental ethics in order to stage the ethical implications of modes of criticism. I then discuss specific parallels between the work of deconstruction and that of environmental ethics, and suggest that a deconstructive spirit is at the heart of environmental philosophy’s recent—and most important—work on the question of “universal consideration.”
24. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 23 > Issue: 2
Mark A. Michael How to Interfere with Nature
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
The principle that we should not interfere with nature plays a prominent role in both popular and academic accounts of environmental ethics. For example, it is often cited to justify the claims that we should not actively manage wilderness areas and that we should not extinguish naturally occurring fires in those areas. It is far from clear, however, exactly what that principle entails for our treatment of species and ecosystems. Does all human interaction with nature amount to interference? If there are different kinds of interference, are they all wrong? Might not there be such a thing as beneficial interference? Can one part of nature interfere with another, and if so, is it morally permissible or forbidden for humans to prevent this kind of interference? These questions can be answered only if we have a clear notion of interference. First, I examine one initially plausible account which takes it to be a kind of cause. One interferes with a species or ecosystem when one alters or redirects it. Second, I answer a crucial question that must be faced with regard to any theory that takes interference to be a kind of cause. If interference involves nothing more than having an effect on an ecosystem, then the activities of practically every species in an ecosystem interfere with it. However, these activities are usually thought of as legitimate or normal ecosystemic change, as essential components of the ecosystem, rather than as interference.Thus, some criterion must be proposed to distinguish between interference and the actions of other species which have an effect on an ecosystem but do not interfere with it. I look at a number of proposals and conclude that no one of them is uniquely correct. Rather, the criterion one employs to understand interference must be determined by one’s projects and goals.
discussion papers
25. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 23 > Issue: 2
Robert Ayres, Jeroen van den Berrgh, John Gowdy Strong versus Weak Sustainability: Economics, Natural Sciences, and Consilience
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
The meaning of sustainability is the subject of intense debate among environmental and resource economists. Perhaps no other issue separates more clearly the traditional economic view from the views of most natural scientists. The debate currently focuses on the substitutability between the economy and the environment or between “natural capital” and “manufactured capital”—a debate captured in terms of weak versus strong sustainability. In this article, we examine the various interpretations of these concepts. We conclude that natural science and economic perspectives on sustainability are inconsistent. The market-based Hartwick-Solow “weak sustainability” approach is far removed from both the ecosystem-based “Holling sustainability” and the “strong sustainability” approach of Daly and others. Each of these sustainability criteria implies a specific valuation approach, and thus an ethical position, to support monetary indicators of sustainability such as a green or sustainable Gross Domestic Product (GDP). The conflict between “weak sustainability” and “strong sustainability” is more evident in the context of centralized than decentralized decision making. In particular, firms selling “services” instead of material goods and regarding the latter as “capital” leads to decisions more or less consistent with either type of sustainability. Finally, we discuss the implications of global sustainability for such open systems as regions and countries. Open systems have not been dealt with systematically for any of the sustainability criteria.
26. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 23 > Issue: 2
Catriona Sandilands Desiring Nature, Queering Ethics
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
I begin from the premise that “environmentalism needs queers.” Given that desire is a significant element in environmental ethics, and that the social organization of sexual-erotic desire has important impacts on human-nonhuman interactions, queer theory promises to aid environmental thought in unraveling and challenging some of these relations. I contribute the following elements to that challenge:the social-sexual organization of natural space; the organizing effects of dominant discourses of reproductive sexuality for both political possibility and bodily experience; and the retrieval (using the works of queer theorist Elizabeth Grosz) of a queer/ecological “erotogenic ethics” based on the blurring of bodily boundaries through eroticized tactile apprehension of the (human and nonhuman) Other.
27. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 23 > Issue: 2
Julian H. Franklin Regan on the Lifeboat Problem: A Defense
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Tom Regan has powerfully argued that all sentient beings having some awareness of self are equal in inherent value, and that their interests where relevant must be given equal treatment. Yet Regan also contends that there are some situations in which the value of different lives should be compared and choice made between them. He supposes an overloaded lifeboat with five occupants in which all will die unless one is thrown overboard. Four of the occupants are human, one is a dog; and Regan holds that it is the dog that ought to go since its life is of less value than that of a human. Regan has thus been sharply attacked for inconsistency. Some say that the comparison of lives, even in this sort of case, contradicts the principle of equal inherent value and introduces a utilitarian calculation of benefit. Othersobject that no ground of choice exists in situations of this sort. But all these criticisms turn out to be unjustified.
book reviews
28. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 23 > Issue: 2
Don Marietta, Jr. The Green Halo: A Bird’s-Eye View of Ecological Ethics
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
29. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 23 > Issue: 2
Rob Friedman Reading the Earth: New Directions in the Study of Literature and the Environment
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
30. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 23 > Issue: 2
Philip Cafaro Dirty Virtues: Emergence of Ecological Virtue Ethics
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
31. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 23 > Issue: 2
Trish Glazebrook Earth Matters: The Earth Sciences, Philosophy, and the Claims of Community
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
32. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 23 > Issue: 2
John Opie Managing the Environment, Managing Ourselves: A History of American Environmental Policy
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
comment
33. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 23 > Issue: 2
Mick Smith Avalanches and Snowballs A Reply to Arne Naess
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
news and notes
34. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 23 > Issue: 1
NEWS AND NOTES
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
features
35. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 23 > Issue: 1
Philip Cafaro Thoreau, Leopold, and Carson: Toward an Environmental Virtue Ethics
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
I argue for an environmental virtue ethics which specifies human excellence and flourishing in relation to nature. I consider Henry David Thoreau, Aldo Leopold, and Rachel Carson as environmental virtue ethicists, and show that these writers share certain ethical positions that any environmental virtue ethics worthy of the name must embrace. These positions include putting economic life in its proper,subordinate place within human life as a whole; cultivating scientific knowledge, while appreciating its limits; extending moral considerability to the nonhuman world; and supporting wilderness protection. I argue that Thoreau, Leopold, and Carson themselves exemplify the potential for cultivating excellence in engagement with wild nature: their lives are among our most powerful arguments for its preservation.
36. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 23 > Issue: 1
Mary Jo Deegan, Christopher W. Podeschi The Ecofeminist Pragmatism of Charlotte Perkins Gilman
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
We read the roots of contemporary ecofeminism through the lens of feminist pragmatism. After indicating the general relation between ecofeminism and feminist pragmatism, we provide a detailed analysis of Charlotte Perkins Gilman’s saga Herland and With Her in Ourland to document the strong connection between these two traditions. Gilman’s congruencies with ecofeminism make clear that she was a forerunner and perhaps a foundation for contemporary ecofeminism. However, further analyses are needed to reveal the full import of this link between ecofeminism and “ecofeminist pragmatism,” as well as bridge the gap between ecofeminist pragmatism and ecopragmatism, including environmental pragmatism.
discussion papers
37. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 23 > Issue: 1
Meg Holden Phenomenology versus Pragmatism
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In this paper, I challenge the work of David Abram, who makes a case for phenomenology as the only philosophical tradition amenable to restoring balanced human-nature relationships. While phenomenology provides a useful conceptual framework for understanding the environmental ethics of oral cultures, this paper considers the tradition of American pragmatism to be more applicable to theenvironmental task at hand: devising an environmental ethic of reform for modern, capitalist, Western culture. The application of phenomenology and pragmatism to environmental ethics is compared according to four main philosophical questions: the essential uncertainty of life, the existence of a human/nature divide, the necessary conditions for claiming truth, and the relative role of metaphysics or imagination and that of science in relating to the world.
38. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 23 > Issue: 1
Ben A. Minteer Intrinsic Value for Pragmatists?
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Conventional wisdom suggests that environmental pragmatists balk at the mere mention of intrinsic value. Indeed, the leading expositor of the pragmatic position in environmental philosophy, Bryan Norton, has delivered withering criticisms of the concept as it has been employed by nonanthropocentrists in the field. Nevertheless, I believe that Norton has left an opening for a recognition of intrinsic value in his arguments, albeit a version that bears little resemblance to most of its traditional incarnations. Drawing from John Dewey’s contextual approach toward moral inquiry, I offer a reconstructed notion of intrinsic value that avoids the metaphysical pitfalls identified by Norton. I argue that this contextual understanding of noninstrumental claims has the advantage of turning our attention toward, and not away from, the critical realm of practice and policy, and that it is especially compatible with the norms of democratic deliberation. By way of example and in defense of my position, I conclude with a rejoinder to Holmes Rolston’s claims about the role of foundational intrinsic value commitments in settling the human-nature dilemma at Royal Chitwan National Park in Nepal.
book reviews
39. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 23 > Issue: 1
Michael McGinnis Eco-Wars: Political Campaigns and Social Movements
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
40. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 23 > Issue: 1
Mark Lacy Social Ecology after Bookchin
view |  rights & permissions | cited by