Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Browse by:



Displaying: 21-40 of 40 documents


features
21. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 2 > Issue: 2
Eugene C. Hargrove Anglo-American Land Use Attitudes
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Environmentalists in the United States are often confronted by rural landowners who feel that they have the right to do whatever they want with their land regardless of the consequences for other human beings or of the damage to the environment. This attitude is traced from its origins in ancient German and Saxon land use practices into the political writings of Thomas Jefferson where it was fused togetherwith John Locke’s theory of property. This view of land and property rights was most influential in the late nineteenth century after the passage of the Homestead Act in 1862 when it was used in the arguments opposing national parks and nature preservation. Today it remains a formidable obstacle to planning and zoning in rural areas, despite unstated underlying assumptions which are either outdated or false.
discussion papers
22. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 2 > Issue: 2
Meredith Williams Rights, Interests, and Moral Equality
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
I discuss Peter Singer’s claim that the interests of animals merit equal consideration with those of human beings. I show that there are morally relevant differences between humans and animals that Singer’s rather narrow utilitarian conception of morality fails to capture. Further, I argue that Singer’s formal conception of moral equality is so thin as to be virtually vacuous and that his attempts to give it moresubstance point to just the kind of differences between humans and animals that undermine his equalitarian thesis.
23. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 2 > Issue: 2
Jay E. Kantor The “Interests” of Natural Objects
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Christopher D. Stone has claimed that natural objects can and should have rights. I accept Stone’s premise that the possession of rights is tied to the possession of interests; however, I argue that the concept of a natural object needs a more careful analysis than is given by Stone. Not everything that Stone calls a natural object is an object “naturally.” Some must be taken as artificial rather than as natural. Thistype of object cannot be said to have intrinsic interests and hence cannot be given rights that can protect “its own sake”-which is the sort of right that Stone focuses on. Further, there are other sorts of natural objects which, although they are objects “naturally,” cannot meaningfully be said to have intrinsic interests, and thus cannot have the sorts of rights that Stone is concerned with. Finally, there are other sorts of natural objects which are objects naturally and which have intrinsic interests, but which are not proper candidates for the possession of rights. The prerequisites for being “owed” rights are the possession of intrinsic interests and the capability to suffer when those interests are interfered with or denied or threatened.
book reviews
24. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 2 > Issue: 2
R. Paul Thompson Sociobiology: Sense or Nonsense?
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
25. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 2 > Issue: 2
Charles R. Magel The Moral Status of Animals
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
26. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 2 > Issue: 2
Sara Shute Why the Green Nigger?: Re-Mything Genesis
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
news and notes
27. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 2 > Issue: 2
NEWS AND NOTES (2)
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
28. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 2 > Issue: 1
NEWS AND NOTES (1)
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
features
29. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 2 > Issue: 1
Donald C. Lee On the Marxian View of the Relationship between Man and Nature
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Marx holds that mankind has developed from nature and in mutual interaction with nature: nature is not an “other” but is man’s body. Capitalism is a necessary stage in mankind’s historical development of the mastery of nature, but it regards nature as an “other” to be exploited. Thus, a further historical development is necessary: the overcoming of the dichotomy between man as subject and nature as object.Capitalism bases its concept of wealth on unnecessary production rather than on socially useful production and on the maximization of true leisure and free and creative activity for all. It creates excess pollution and depletes nonrenewable resources as a result of this wasteful, exploitative, unnecessary production. A Marxian solution to environmental problems involves the replacement of capitalism with a rational humane, environmentally unalienated social order. Unfortunately, the actual practice of Marxism has not generally been in accord with its own theory. Such rational, humane social orders have not yet been instituted, but they must be soon. We must take one aspect of Marx’s ideas to its logical conclusion: Marxist practice has been, at best, homocentric, but now it must overcome that limitation and truly see nature as our “body.” Marxism must become ecologically aware; mankind must become the steward of its “body”: the ecosystem upon which it depends and which now depends upon it for its health (homeostasis).
30. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 2 > Issue: 1
Alastair S. Gunn Why Should We Care about Rare Species?
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Concern for the fate of rare species leads us to ask why the extermination of species is wrong. No satisfactory account can be given in terms of animal rights, and a speciesist perspective can yield at best only a case for preservation of those species which enough people happen to care about. An attempt is made to analyze the concept of rarity, and its relation to value. Finally, it is suggested that the problem can be resolved only in terms of an environmental ethic, according to which the existence of each species, and of ecological wholes, is held to have intrinsic value.
news and notes
31. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 2 > Issue: 1
NEWS AND NOTES (2)
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
discussion papers
32. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 2 > Issue: 1
Daniel L. Dustin, Leo H McAvoy Hardining National Parks
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
The “tragedy of the commons” argument developed by Garrett Hardin is applied to problems associated with the increasing use of the national parks in the United States. The relevance of his argument to such problems is illustrated by a discussion of the proposals included in the recent Draft General Management Plan for Yosemite National Park. Implications for the future management of Yosemite andother public recreation resources conclude the article.
33. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 2 > Issue: 1
J. A. Doeleman On the Social Rate of Discount: The Case for Macroenvironmental Policy
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Concern for the rapidly growing scale and intensity of the human exploitation of the environment, in particular the alienation of natural ecosystems, but also resource exhaustion, pollution, and congestion, leads one to wonder about the short time. horizons allowed for in decision making. Time preference is dictated by the rate of interest, allowing in practice a horizon often not exceeding several decades. I argue that this is unsatisfactory. Some minimal social rate of discount should not be enforced. Instead, it is more feasible to set absolute environmental standards, thereby introducing quantity constraints on our decision making, within which time preference can be permitted to find its own level. This acknowledges that the myopia of human vision may not be a flaw but rather a biological design which has served us weIl in evolution. It may, therefore, be better to change the rules by introducing self-imposed collective constraints than to try to change the shortsightedness of people in their day-to-day grass-roots decision making.
34. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 2 > Issue: 1
W. Murray Hunt Are Mere Things Morally Considerable?
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Kenneth Goodpaster has criticized ethicists like Feinberg and Frankena for too narrowly circumscribing the range of moral considerability, urging instead that “nothing short of the condition of being alive” is a satisfactory criterion. Goodpaster overlooks at least one crucial objection: that his own “condition of being alive” may aIso be too narrow a criterion of moral considerability, since “being in existence” is at least as plausible and nonarbitrary a criterion as is Goodpaster’s. I show that each of the arguments that Goodpaster musters in support of his criterion can be used equally weIl to bolster “being in existence” as a test of moral considerability. Moreover, I argue that “being in existence” appears to be a stronger criterion overall, since it is broader. Until or unless a fuller justification is forthcoming of “being alive” as a satisfactory criterion of moral considerability-a justification which must demonstrate that “mere things,” included under the condition of “being in existence,” do not deserve moral consideration--Goodpaster’sthesis is confronted with a serious problem.
35. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 2 > Issue: 1
Anthony J. Povilitis On Assigning Rights to Animals and Nature
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Watson argues that living entities do not have intrinsic or primary rights, such as the right to existence, unless they are capable of fulfilling reciprocal duties in a self-conscious manner. I suggest that (1) Watson’s “reciprocity framework” for rights and duties is excessively anthropocentric, (2) that it is founded on the incorrect assumption that the Golden Rule refers to mutual rather than individual duties, and (3) that Watson arbitrarily equates moral rights with primary rights. Since “intrinsic” rights are, in effect, assigned rights, the assignment of rights to a given entity is viewed as a function of its perceived value. Thus, in emphasizing differences between man and other living entities, Watson chooses Cartesian values in assigning rights. Conversely, the ecological and evolutionary relatedness of living things forms the basis for considering rights within the naturalist tradition.
36. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 2 > Issue: 1
Russell Goodman Taoism and Ecology
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Although they were in part otherworldly mystics, the Taoists of ancient China were also keen observers of nature; in fact, they were important early Chinese scientists. I apply Taoist principles to some current ecological questions. The principles surveyed include reversion, the constancy of cyclical change, wu wei (“actionless activity”), and the procurement of power by abandoning the attempt to “take” it. On the basis of these principles, I argue that Taoists would have favored such contemporary options as passive solar energy and organic fanning.
book reviews
37. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 2 > Issue: 1
David L. Hull On Human Nature
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
38. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 2 > Issue: 1
John B. Cobb, Jr. Animal Rights: A Christian Assessment of Man’s Treatment of Animals
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
referees
39. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 2 > Issue: 1
REFEREES
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
comment
40. Environmental Ethics: Volume > 2 > Issue: 1
COMMENT
view |  rights & permissions | cited by