Cover of International Philosophical Quarterly
Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Browse by:



Displaying: 21-40 of 52 documents


articles
21. International Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 55 > Issue: 3
Zemian Zheng Self-deception, Sincerity (Cheng), and Zhu Xi’s Last Word
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Zhu Xi believes that if one attains genuine knowledge of good and evil, one will do good and avoid evil wholeheartedly. As a result, the phenomena of self-deception and akrasia (weakness of will) pose a challenge to his moral psychology. On his deathbed, he revised his commentary on self-deception and sincerity in the book Great Learning. His final explanatory model could be understood as a moderate version of intentionalism: a self-deceiver tacitly allows room for thoughts that run counter to his ethical beliefs, even if this potentially undermines his integrity. This model highlights two major causes for self-deception: uncritical self-trust and the dubious ethical status of first-order desires. Zhu contends that thoughts cannot render themselves sincere on their own. As a remedy, he advocates an open-minded dialogue with the cultural world documented in the classics so as to avoid the myopia of the self.
contemporary currents
22. International Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 55 > Issue: 3
Earl Stanley B. Fronda Supernaturalism is Unwittingly Naturalistic
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Supernaturalism is a philosophical position used in modernity that employs the “supernatural” to explain certain “natural” phenomena. The supernatural is defined by circumscription from the natural. But the line that is supposed to delineate the supernatural from the natural is porous and tenuous, to the point that the distinction between the two becomes a matter of no import. This renders vacuous the concept of the supernatural as well as the concept of the natural. Supernaturalism ends up naturalizing what is supposed to be supernatural. But there is a conception of the supernatural (introduced by John Scotus Eriugena and sent into theological circulation by Thomas Aquinas) that predates the modernist one. Benchmarked against this conception, the God posited by supernaturalism in the modern sense is not supernatural.
book reviews
23. International Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 55 > Issue: 3
Joseph W. Koterski, S.J. Political Augustinianism: Modern Interpretations of Augustine’s Political Thought. By Michael J. S. Bruno
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
24. International Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 55 > Issue: 3
Virginia L. Arbery Comic Cure for Delusional Democracy. By Gene Fendt
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
25. International Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 55 > Issue: 3
James M. Jacobs Human Action in Thomas Aquinas, John Duns Scotus, and William of Ockham. By Thomas M. Osborne Jr.
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
26. International Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 55 > Issue: 3
Books Received
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
27. International Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 55 > Issue: 2
About Our Contributors
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
articles
28. International Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 55 > Issue: 2
Mark K. Spencer Aristotelian Substance and Personalistic Subjectivity
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Many personalists have argued that an adequate account of the human person must include an account of subjectivity as irreducible to anything objectively definable. The personalists contend that Aristotle lacks such an account and claim that he fails to meet three criteria that a theory of the human person must fulfill in order to have an account of subjectivity as irreducible. I show first that some later Aristotelians fulfill these criteria, and then that Aristotle himself also does so. He describes four characteristics of human subjectivity that are considered crucial by many personalists. I do this through an interpretation of Aristotle’s accounts of substantial actualities, nous, friendship, and beauty.
29. International Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 55 > Issue: 2
Matej Sušnik Strong Motivational Internalism
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Strong motivational internalists claim that the relation between moral judgment and motivation is necessary. It is widely accepted that strong motivational internalism is false because it cannot accommodate various phenomena from common experience. In order to make room for these phenomena, motivational internalists usually propose the weak formulation of their thesis. In the first part of the paper I differentiate between several versions of both strong and weak motivational internalism. In the second part I argue that the reasons for endorsing weak motivational internalism of any form are not compelling.
30. International Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 55 > Issue: 2
Peter Furlong Aquinas, the Principle of Alternative Possibilities, and Augustine’s Axiom
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
According to the highly controversial “Principle of Alternative Possibilities,” an agent is morally responsible for an action only if he could have done otherwise. In this paper, I will investigate whether Aquinas accepts this principle. I will begin by arguing that if one grants Aquinas’s theory of human action, Frankfurt-style counter-examples do not succeed. For this reason, it is necessary to investigate various texts in order to discover how Aquinas views this principle. Although he does not explicitly discuss it, he does discuss an axiom (taken from Augustine) that is similar to this principle in various ways. I eventually conclude that, even if Aquinas would reject a strict understanding of PAP, he would only demand a relatively common modification of it.
31. International Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 55 > Issue: 2
David McPherson Cosmic Outlooks and Neo-Aristotelian Virtue Ethics
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
I examine Bernard Williams’s forceful challenge that evolutionary science has done away with the sort of teleological worldview that is needed in order to make sense of an Aristotelian virtue ethic perspective. I also consider Rosalind Hursthouse’s response to Williams and argue that it is not sufficient. My main task is to show what is needed in order to meet Williams’s challenge. First, I argue that we need a deeper exploration of the first-personal evaluative standpoint from within our human form of life than we find in Hursthouse’s ethical naturalist perspective. In particular, we need to recognize the important role of “strong evaluation” for identifying what is noblest and best about us as human beings, for this will enable us to address the “mixed bag” problem of human nature. Second, I argue—contra John McDowell’s quietism—that in order to make sense of such a normative account of human nature we must overcome Williams’s tragic cosmic outlook according to which human life is seen as ultimately without meaning and purpose.
32. International Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 55 > Issue: 2
Gabriel Gottlieb Fichte’s Deduction of the External World
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
The essay provides a new interpretation of Fichte’s deduction of the external world that considers the argument to be motivated not by epistemic concerns but by concerns about the possibility of freedom. In defending this view, I critically examine Frederick Beiser’s reconstruction of Fichte’s deduction, which characterizes the argument as refuting external world skepticism, exactly the threat by which (I argue) Fichte is not troubled. I claim that Fichte is troubled by ethical skepticism, the view that the freedom required for self-consciousness is not possible. Establishing the possibility of the freedom involved in self-consciousness requires an external world suitable for such a form of freedom. An implication of this claim is that the world that Fichte deduces is an intersubjective or social world.
33. International Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 55 > Issue: 2
Dale Snow Translation and Interpretative Introduction of “Treatise on the Relationship of the Real and the Ideal in Nature” (1806) by F. W. J. Schelling
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
The “Treatise on the Relationship of the Real and the Ideal in Nature, or the Development of the First Principles of the Philosophy of Nature and the Principles of Gravity and Light” is one of the last essays on Naturphilosophie that Schelling wrote. It was a topic that had occupied his attention since 1796, and as such it marks the end of an era. It is distinguished by its unusual approach to the problem of matter, which becomes, in his discussion, the problem of force or energy. Without being able to avail himself of the language of the conservation of energy or mass, it can be argued that Schelling makes a valiant attempt to express that insight, using the terminology of the bond and the entities bound by it. The text reaffirms Schelling’s strong affinities with Spinoza, anticipates Schopenhauer, and continues his quarrel with Fichte.
book reviews
34. International Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 55 > Issue: 2
Christopher M. Cullen, S.J. Nature and Grace: A New Approach to Thomistic Ressourcement. By Andrew Dean Swafford
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
35. International Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 55 > Issue: 2
Brian Gregor Kierkegaard’s Journals and Notebooks, Vol. 6: Journals NB11–NB14. Edited by Niels Jørgen Cappelørn, Alastair Hannay, David Kangas, Bruce H. Kirmmse, George Pattison, Joel D.S. Rasmussen, Vanessa Rumble, and K. Brian Söderquist
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
36. International Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 55 > Issue: 2
Joseph W. Koterski, S.J. Potentiality: Metaphysical and Bioethical Dimensions. Edited by John P. Lizza
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
37. International Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 55 > Issue: 2
Joseph G. Trabbic In the Self’s Place: The Approach of Saint Augustine. By Jean-Luc Marion. Translated by Jeffrey L. Kosky
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
38. International Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 55 > Issue: 2
Books Received
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
39. International Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 55 > Issue: 1
About Our Contributors
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
articles
40. International Philosophical Quarterly: Volume > 55 > Issue: 1
Tom Angier Happiness: Overcoming the Skill Model
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
I argue that the theory of happiness now dominant among philosophers embraces a flawed, technicizing model that represents happiness as a set of mental states produced by actions and events. This view contrasts with Aristotle’s conception, according to which happiness is not produced by (but is tantamount to) long-term activity and incorporates (but is not reducible to) a set of mental states. I then go on to criticize the skill model of happiness on three main grounds. First, unlike the Aristotelian model, it necessarily instrumentalizes activity while setting no principled limit to the manipulation of human action and experience. Second, and again contra Aristotle, it privileges an efficient (rather than formal) conception of causation while obscuring the way in which happiness is inextricably grounded in its conditions, which in turn has various deleterious upshots. Third and finally, the skill model yields a highly questionable notion of happiness as measurable.