Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Browse by:



Displaying: 21-40 of 48 documents


articles
21. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 70 > Issue: 2
Gene Witmer, William Butchard, Kelly Trogdon Intrinsicality without Naturalness
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Rae Langton and David Lewis have proposed an account of “intrinsic property” that makes use of two notions: being independent of accompaniment and being natural. We find the appeal to the first of these promising; the second notion, however, we find mystifying. In this paper we argue that the appeal to naturalness is not acceptable and offer an alternative definition of intrinsicality. The alternative definition makes crucial use of a notion commonly used by philosophers, namely, the notion of one property being had in virtue of another property. We defend our account against three arguments for thinking that this “in virtue of” notion is unacceptable in this context. We also take a look at a variety of cases in which the definition might be applied and defend it against potential counterexamples. The upshot, we think, is a modest but adequate account of what we understand by “intrinsic property.”
22. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 70 > Issue: 2
Luciano Floridi Is Semantic Information Meaningful Data?
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
There is no consensus yet on the definition of semantic information. This paper contributes to the current debate by criticising and revising the Standard Definition of semantic Information (SDI) as meaningful data, in favour of the Dretske-Grice approach: meaningful and well-formed data constitute semantic information only if they also qualify as contingently truthful. After a brief introduction, SDI is criticised for providing necessary but insufficient conditions for the definition of semantic information. SDI is incorrect because truth-values do not supervene on semantic information, and misinformation (that is, false semantic information) is not a type of semantic information, but pseudo-information, that is not semantic information at all. This is shown by arguing that none of the reasons for interpreting misinformation as a type of semantic information is convincing, whilst there are compelling reasons to treat it as pseudo-information. As a consequence, SDI is revised to include a necessary truth-condition. The last section summarises the main results of the paper and indicates some interesting areas of application of the revised definition.
23. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 70 > Issue: 2
Donald L. M. Baxter Altruism, Grief, and Identity
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
The divide between oneself and others has made altruism seem irrational to some thinkers, as Sidgwick points out. I use characterizations of grief, especially by St. Augustine, to question the divide, and use a composition-as-identity metaphysics of parts and wholes to make literal sense of those characterizations.
24. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 70 > Issue: 2
Brian Kierland, Bradley Monton Minimizing Inaccuracy for Self-Locating Beliefs
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
One’s inaccuracy for a proposition is defined as the squared difference between the truth value (1 or 0) of the proposition and the credence (or subjective probability, or degree of belief) assigned to the proposition. One should have the epistemic goal of minimizing the expected inaccuracies of one’s credences. We show that the method of minimizing expected inaccuracy can be used to solve certain probability problems involving information loss and self-locating beliefs (where a self-locating belief of a temporal part of an individual is a belief about where or when that temporal part is located). We analyze the Sleeping Beauty problem, the duplication version of the Sleeping Beauty problem, and various related problems.
25. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 70 > Issue: 2
John Hawthorne Chance and Counterfactuals
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Suppose the world is chancy. The worry arises that most ordinary counterfactuals are false. This paper examines David Lewis’ strategy for rescuing such counterfactuals, and argues that it is highly problematic.
discussions
26. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 70 > Issue: 2
Peter J. Markie Easy Knowledge
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Stewart Cohen has recently presented solutions to two forms of what he calls “The Problem of Easy Knowledge” (“Basic Knowledge and the Problem of Easy Knowledge,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, LXV, 2, September 2002, pp. 309-329). I offer alternative solutions. Like Cohen’s, my solutions allow for basic knowledge. Unlike his, they do not require that we distinguish between animal and reflective knowledge, restrict the applicability of closure under known entailments, or deny the ability of basic knowledge to combine with self-knowledge to provide inductive evidential support. My solution to the closure version of the problem covers a variation on the problem that is immune to Cohen’s approach. My response to the bootstrapping version presents reasons to question whether the problem case, as Cohen presents it, is even possible, and, assuming it is, my solution avoids a false implication of Cohen’s own. The key to my solutions for both versions is the distinction between an inference’s transferring epistemic support, on the one hand, and its not begging the question against skeptics, on the other.
27. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 70 > Issue: 2
Stewart Cohen Why Basic Knowledge is Easy Knowledge
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
book symposium
28. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 70 > Issue: 2
Timothy Williamson Précis of Knowledge and its Limits
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
29. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 70 > Issue: 2
Anthony Brueckner Knowledge, Evidence, and Skepticism According to Williamson
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
30. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 70 > Issue: 2
Earl Conee The Comforts of Home
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
31. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 70 > Issue: 2
John Hawthorne Knowledge and Evidence
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
32. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 70 > Issue: 2
Stephen Yablo Prime Causation
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
33. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 70 > Issue: 2
Timothy Williamson Replies to Commentators
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
critical notices
34. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 70 > Issue: 2
Michael J. Zimmerman Deontic Morality and Control
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
35. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 70 > Issue: 2
Frederick F. Schmitt Social Empiricism
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
36. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 70 > Issue: 2
Michael Gorr A Theory of Freedom: From the Psychology to the Politics of Agency
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
articles
37. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 70 > Issue: 1
Michael Della Rocca Descartes, the Cartesian Circle, and Epistemology Without God
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
This paper defends an interpretation of Descartes according to which he sees us as having normative (and not merely psychological) certainty of all clear and distinct ideas during the period in which they are apprehended clearly and distinctly. However, on this view, a retrospective doubt about clear and distinct ideas is possible. This interpretation allows Descartes to avoid the Cartesian Circle in an effective way and also shows that Descartes is surprisingly, in some respects, an epistemological externalist. The paper goes on to defend this interpretation against some powerful philosophical objections by Margaret WiIson and others by showing how Descartes’ doctrine of the creation of the eternal truths can be brought in to support his epistemology. This doctrine and other analogous positions in Descartes can also reveal that Descartes, again surprisingly, takes important steps toward doing epistemology without direct appeal to God and God’s veracity.
38. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 70 > Issue: 1
Michael Ridge Universalizability for Collective Rational Agents: A Critique of Agent-relativism
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
This paper contends that a Kantian universalizability constraint on theories of practical reason in conjunction with the possibility of collective rational agents entails the surprisingly strong conclusion that no fully agent-relative theory of practical reason can be sound. The basic point is that a Kantian universalizability constraint, the thesis that all reasons for action are agent-relative and the possibility of collective rational agents gives rise to a contradiction. This contradiction can be avoided by either rejecting Kantian universalizability, the possibility of collective rational agents, or the tenability of a fully agent-relative theory of practical reason; we cannot have all three.
39. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 70 > Issue: 1
Eli Hirsch Physical-Object Ontology, Verbal Disputes, and Common Sense
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Two main claims are defended in this paper: first, that typical disputes in the literature about the ontology of physical objects are merely verbal; second, that the proper way to resolve these disputes is by appealing to common sense or ordinary language. A verbal dispute is characterized not in terms of private idiolects, but in terms of different linguistic communities representing different positions. If we imagine a community that makes Chisholm’s mereological essentialist assertions, and another community that makes Lewis’s four-dimensionalist assertions, the members of each community speak the truth in their respective languages. This follows from an application of the principle of interpretive charity to the two communities.
40. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research: Volume > 70 > Issue: 1
Erik J. Olsson Not Giving the Skeptic a Hearing: Pragmatism and Radical Doubt Lund University, Sweden
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Pragmatist responses to radical skepticism do not receive much attention In contemporary analytic epistemology. This observation is my motivation for undertaking a search for a coherent pragmatist reply to radical doubt, one that can compete, in terms of clarity and sophistication, with the currently most popular approaches, such as contextualism and relevant alternatives theory. As my point of departure I take the texts of C. S. Peirce and William James. The Jamesian response is seen to consist in the application of a wager argument to the skeptical issue in analogy with Pascal’s wager. The Peircean strategy, on the other hand, is to attempt a direct rejection of one of the skeptic’s main premises: that we do not know we are not deceived. I argue that while the Jamesian attempt is ultimately incoherent, Peirce’s argument contains the core of a detailed and characteristically “pragmatic” rebuttal of skepticism, one that deserves to be taken seriously in the contemporary debate.