Cover of Social Theory and Practice
Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Browse by:



Displaying: 21-40 of 41 documents


book reviews
21. Social Theory and Practice: Volume > 36 > Issue: 3
Amy R. Baehr Toward a Humanist Justice: The Political Philosophy of Susan Moller Okin
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
22. Social Theory and Practice: Volume > 36 > Issue: 3
Kristján Kristjánsson Desert and Virtue: A Theory of Intrinsic Value
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
23. Social Theory and Practice: Volume > 36 > Issue: 2
Lisa Rivera Worthy Lives
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Susan Wolf's paper "Meaning and Morality" draws our attention to the fact that Williams's objection to Kantian morality is primarily a concern about a possible conflict between morality and that which gives our lives meaning. I argue that the force of Williams's objection requires a more precise understanding of meaning as dependent on our intention to make our lives themselves worthwhile. It is not meaning simpliciter that makes Williams's objective persuasive but rather meaning as arising out of our positive evaluation of the value of our lives as a whole. This type of meaning has a normative element: it involves a person's deep-seated commitment to make her actions consistent with ends that confer worth on her life itself. The more significant conflict with morality lies in the conflict between the normative force of moral requirements and the normative force of the need to have a life that is itself worthwhile.
24. Social Theory and Practice: Volume > 36 > Issue: 2
Brian McElwee The Appeal of Self-Ownership
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In this paper, I argue that the appeal of a principle of self-ownership is grounded in the specially intimate relationship that each of us has with our body. I argue that once we appreciate the source of the appeal of a claim of self-ownership, we can see how a differently shaped set of strong rights over our body can do justice to the considerations that ground this appeal, without committing us to the most controversial implications of a claim of self-ownership.
25. Social Theory and Practice: Volume > 36 > Issue: 2
Daniel Engster The Place of Parenting within a Liberal Theory of Justice: The Private Parenting Model, Parental Licenses, or Public Parenting Support?
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Parenting has an ambiguous place within the liberal tradition. On the one hand, liberal theorists have traditionally portrayed it as a private activity. On the other hand, they have also acknowledged the need for some public regulation of parenting in order to protect children’s interests. Some theorists have suggested that this ambiguity within liberalism can be best resolved by implementing parental licensing plans that would limit childrearing opportunities strictly to individuals who could prove their psychological, moral, and financial competency to raise children well. In this article, I critique parental licensing schemes from a liberal perspective and argue that public parenting support, including paid parenting leaves, public childcare subsidies, and the like, is more consistent with liberal values and, in fact, a necessary component of any coherent liberal theory of justice.
26. Social Theory and Practice: Volume > 36 > Issue: 2
Todd Calder Shared Responsibility, Global Structural Injustice, and Restitution
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
This paper argues that even the most virtuous people living in affluent Western countries share responsibility for injustices suffered by poor people living in developing countries. The argument of the paper draws on a moral principle that underlies the law of restitution: the principle of unjust enrichment. The paper argues that denizens of affluent Western countries have benefited unjustly from injustices suffered by poor people living in developing countries and that they have a moral responsibility to pay back their unjust gains.
27. Social Theory and Practice: Volume > 36 > Issue: 2
Nahshon Perez Why Tolerating Illiberal Groups is Often Incoherent: On Internal Minorities, Liberty, “Shared Understandings,” and Skepticism
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
This article suggests that in cases in which illiberal groups face internal disagreement, plausible liberal arguments for toleration of such groups are hard to find. Since internal disagreement is widespread, this article proposes that arguments that attempt to justify toleration vis-à-vis illiberal groups are mostly incoherent views. I differentiate this argument from a different issue, namely, whether there is a justification for an external liberal agent to actively intervene in cases in which there exists a justification for lack of toleration.
review essay
28. Social Theory and Practice: Volume > 36 > Issue: 2
Jonathan Quong Justice Beyond Equality
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
This essay reviews G.A. Cohen’s final major work, Rescuing Justice and Equality. In the book, Cohen challenges the Rawlsian account of the content and the concept of justice. This essay offers a summary of Cohen’s main arguments, and develops objections to several of those arguments, particularly Cohen’s claim that his proposed egalitarian ethos is not vulnerable to a well-known trilemma (liberty, equality, efficiency) that might be pressed against it. The essay’s final section offers critical reflections on the important differences between Cohen’s and Rawls’s views about the nature of justice, and suggests that Cohen’s view may not be helpful if we believe justice is a complex value that includes considerations other than distributive equality.
book reviews
29. Social Theory and Practice: Volume > 36 > Issue: 2
Mira Bachvarova Ownership, Authority, and Self-Determination
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
30. Social Theory and Practice: Volume > 36 > Issue: 2
Karen Green Canon Fodder: Historical Women Political Thinkers
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
31. Social Theory and Practice: Volume > 36 > Issue: 2
Glen Pettigrove I Was Wrong: The Meanings of Apologies
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
32. Social Theory and Practice: Volume > 36 > Issue: 1
Helga Varden Lockean Freedom and the Proviso’s Appeal to Scientific Knowledge
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
I argue in this paper that Locke and contemporary Lockeans underestimate the problems involved in their frequent, implicit assumption that when we apply the proviso we use the latest scientific knowledge of natural resources, technology, and the economy’s operations. Problematic for these theories is that much of the pertinent knowledge used is obtained through particular persons’ labor. If the knowledge obtained through individuals’ labor must be made available to everyone and if particular persons’ new knowledge affects the proviso’s proper application, then some end up without freedom to pursue their own ends and some find their freedom subject to others’ arbitrary will.
33. Social Theory and Practice: Volume > 36 > Issue: 1
Steve Daskal Libertarianism Left and Right, the Lockean Proviso, and the Reformed Welfare State
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
This paper explores the implications of libertarianism for welfare policy. There are two central arguments. First, the paper argues that if one adopts a libertarian framework, it makes most sense to be a Lockean right-libertarian. Second, the paper argues that this form of libertarianism leads to the endorsement of a fairly extensive set of redistributive welfare programs. Specifically, the paper argues that Lockean right-libertarians are committed to endorsing welfare programs under which the receipt of benefits is conditional on meeting a work requirement, and also endorsing some form of publicly funded jobs of last resort for potential welfare recipients.
34. Social Theory and Practice: Volume > 36 > Issue: 1
Yvonne Chiu Uniform Exceptions and Rights Violations
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Non-uniformed combat morally infringes on civilians’ fundamental right to immunity and exacts an impermissible form of unofficial conscription that is morally prohibited even if the civilians knowingly consent to it. It is often argued that revolutionary groups burdened by resource disparities relative to the state or who claim alternative sources of political legitimacy (such as national self-determination or the constitution of a political collective) are justified in using unconventional tactics such as non-uniformed combat. Neither those reasons nor the provision of public goods, however, are sufficient to justify such rights violations and this form of conscription, and it calls into question the suitability of current international legal protections for the non-uniformed.
35. Social Theory and Practice: Volume > 36 > Issue: 1
Jules Holroyd Punishment and Justice
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Should the state punish its disadvantaged citizens who have committed crimes? Duff has recently argued that where disadvantage persists the state loses its authority to hold individuals to account and to punish for criminal wrongdoings. I here scrutinize Duff’s argument for the claim that social justice is a precondition for the legitimacy of state punishment. I sharpen an objection to Duff’s argument: with his framework, we seem unable to block the implausible conclusion that where disadvantage persists the state lacks the authority to punish any citizen for any crime. I then set out an alternative line of argument in support of the claim that social deprivation can threaten the states legitimate punitive authority. I argue that a penal system must incorporate certain proportionality principles, and that these principles cannot both be met where citizens suffer from deprivation.
36. Social Theory and Practice: Volume > 36 > Issue: 1
Joseph Millum How Do We Acquire Parental Rights?
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In this paper I develop an account of how parental rights are acquired. According to this investment theory, parental rights are generated by the performance of parental work. Thus, those who successfully parent a child have the right to continue to do so, and to exclude others from so doing. The account derives from a more general principle of desert that applies outside the domain of parenthood. It also has some interesting implications for the attribution of moral parenthood. In particular, it implies that genetic relationships per se are irrelevant to parental rights and that it is possible to have more than two moral parents.
37. Social Theory and Practice: Volume > 36 > Issue: 1
Erik Malmqvist, Kristin Zeiler Cultural Norms, the Phenomenology of Incorporation, and the Experience of Having a Child Born with Ambiguous Sex
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
The influence of pervasive cultural norms on people’s actions constitutes a longstanding problem for autonomy theory. On the one hand, such norms often seem to elude the kind of reflection that autonomous agency requires. On the other hand, they are hardly entirely beyond the pale of autonomy: people do sometimes reflect critically on them and resist them. This paper draws on phenomenological accounts of embodiment in order to reconcile these observations. We suggest that pervasive cultural norms exert a strong and elusive, but occasionally resistible, influence because they are incorporated – they operate on the largely pre-reflective bodily level of human existence. As an illustration we discuss parental decisions about surgery for children born with unclear sex, decisions permeated by deeply entrenched norms about sexual difference and genital appearance.
book reviews
38. Social Theory and Practice: Volume > 36 > Issue: 1
Paul Bloomfield The Normative Web: An Argument for Moral Realism
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
39. Social Theory and Practice: Volume > 36 > Issue: 1
James W. Boettcher The Autonomy of Morality
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
40. Social Theory and Practice: Volume > 36 > Issue: 1
Ruth Sample Illusion of Consent: Engaging with Carole Pateman
view |  rights & permissions | cited by