Cover of The Acorn
Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Browse by:



Displaying: 41-60 of 295 documents


book reviews
41. The Acorn: Volume > 19 > Issue: 2
Gail Presbey Between Gandhi and Black Lives Matter: The Interreligious Roots of Civil Rights Activism: Review of Sarah Azaransky, This Worldwide Struggle: Religion and the International Roots of the Civil Rights Movement
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
42. The Acorn: Volume > 19 > Issue: 2
Tom H. Hastings The Grotesque Cost of Militarism’s Syndemics: Review of Catherine Lutz and Andrea Mazzarino, editors, War and Health: The Medical Consequences of the Wars in Iraq and Afghanistan
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
43. The Acorn: Volume > 19 > Issue: 2
Will Barnes Nonviolence as Manic Rupture of Individualism: Review of Judith Butler, The Force of Nonviolence: An Ethico-Political Bind
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
44. The Acorn: Volume > 19 > Issue: 2
Contributors
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
45. The Acorn: Volume > 19 > Issue: 2
Acknowledgments
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
46. The Acorn: Volume > 19 > Issue: 1
Greg Moses, Sanjay Lal From Canons of Peace to Shoots of Resistance: Editors' Introduction
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
features
47. The Acorn: Volume > 19 > Issue: 1
Douglas Allen Mahatma Gandhi’s Philosophy of Nonviolence and Truth: The Key Values and Concepts for Gandhi 150 and the Future
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
In commemoration of the 150th birthday of M. K. ‘Mahatma’ Gandhi, Douglas Allen, author of Gandhi After 9/11, presents an overview of Gandhi’s philosophy focused on two key values or concepts: Truth (Satya) and Nonviolence (Ahimsa). The presentation is offered as an alternative to non-Gandhians, anti-Gandhians, or reactionary Gandhians who often over-idealized the man and his philosophy. With respect to Ahimsa or Nonviolence, it may be easy to see how the value works against overt, physical violence. However, for Gandhi such examples are only a small part of violence overall. For Gandhi, violence and nonviolence are multidimensional, encompassing our personal ego-driven desires and our widespread economic exploitations. Each dimension of violence or nonviolence is both causal and conditioning, beginning with the experiences of children. Ahimsa should therefore be approached as relational and interconnected. Gandhi approaches the structural violence of the status quo by insisting upon transformative structural nonviolence. Gandhi’s approach to Truth or Satya requires a distinction between Absolute Truth and relative truth. Although Gandhi works with an experiential knowledge of Absolute Truth, he was not an absolutist. Gandhi’s primary focus was upon relative truth, which yields temporary and imperfect ‘glimpses’ of the absolute. In relations with others, we seek kinship with bearers of relative truth. This is the significance of Gandhi’s claim that means and ends are intertwined. With others we seek mutual discovery of relative truths generating greater relative truth. Gandhi’s well known Absolute Nonviolence may prevent us from apprehending its relationship to relative transformations in contextual situations.
48. The Acorn: Volume > 19 > Issue: 1
Court D. Lewis, Gregory L. Bock, David Boersema, Jennifer Kling Author Court D. Lewis Meets Critics on Repentance and the Right to Forgiveness
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Court D. Lewis, author of Repentance and the Right to Forgiveness, presents a rights-based theory of ethics grounded in eirenéism, a needs-based theory of rights (inspired by Nicholas Wolterstorff) that seeks peaceful flourishing for all moral agents. This approach creates a moral relationship between victims and wrongdoers such that wrongdoers owe victims compensatory obligations. However, one further result is that wrongdoers may be owed forgiveness by victims. This leads to the “repugnant implication” that victims may be wrongdoers who do not forgive. Author Lewis addresses the “repugnant implication” by showing that victims are obligated to work toward forgiveness, if not forgiveness itself. Critic Gregory L. Bock argues that victims are not the only ones who can forgive, that the personal dimensions of forgiveness are overlooked, and that the force of the “repugnancy implication” may be questioned. Instead of rights-based eirenéism, Bock supports a virtue ethics framework. Instead of rights-based eirenéism, Bock encourages virtue ethics. Critic David Boersema raises questions about the binding nature of relationships, the dependency of flourishing upon forgiveness, and the nature of needs or rights. Boersema also questions the wisdom of a rights-based approach to forgiveness. Critic Jennifer Kling asks whether a rights-based approach is necessary to ground obligations to meet the needs of others: why not an ethics of care? If a rights-based approach is taken, perhaps a wrongdoer is obligated to not make forgiveness a life good. By disengaging this obligation, we avoid constraining a victim’s work toward forgiveness, especially when the wrongdoing is oppressive. Author Lewis responds to these objections.
reviews
49. The Acorn: Volume > 19 > Issue: 1
Matthew Rukgaber Peace and the Unity of Kant’s Critical Project: Review of Philip J. Rossi, The Ethical Commonwealth in History: Peace-making as the Moral Vocation of Humanity
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
50. The Acorn: Volume > 19 > Issue: 1
Charles K. Fink Acting Out the Kingdom of God: Review of Predrag Cicovacki and Heidi Nada Grek, editors, Tolstoy and Spirituality
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
51. The Acorn: Volume > 19 > Issue: 1
Marilyn Fischer Hull House, the Pullman Strike, and Tolstoy: Documenting the Work of Jane Addams: Review of Mary Lynn McCree Bryan, Maree de Angury, and Ellen Skerrett, editors, The Selected Papers of Jane Addams, Volume III: Creating Hull-House and an International Presence, 1889–1900
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
52. The Acorn: Volume > 19 > Issue: 1
Paula Smithka Resisting the Many Faces of Violence: Review of Jennifer Kling, editor, Pacifism, Politics, and Feminism: Intersections and Innovations
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
53. The Acorn: Volume > 19 > Issue: 1
Walter Kendall A New Story for a Politics of Belonging: Review of George Monbiot, Out of the Wreckage: A New Politics for an Age of Crisis
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
54. The Acorn: Volume > 19 > Issue: 1
Court Lewis The Gift of Kwe: A Present of Radical Resurgence: Review of Leanne Betasamosake Simpson, As We Have Always Done: Indigenous Freedom Through Radical Resistance
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
55. The Acorn: Volume > 19 > Issue: 1
Contributors
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
56. The Acorn: Volume > 18 > Issue: 1/2
Greg Moses Pacifism and Nonviolence as Philosophical Mandate
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
articles
57. The Acorn: Volume > 18 > Issue: 1/2
Andrew Fiala The Pacifist Tradition and Pacifism as Transformative and Critical Theory
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Pacifism is often painted into a corner as an absolute rejection of all violence and war. Such a dogmatic and negative formulation of pacifism does leave us with pacifism as a morally problematic position. But pacifism is not best understood as a negative claim. Nor is pacifism best understood as a singular or monistic concept. Rather, there is a “pacifist tradition” that is grounded in an affirmative claim about the importance of nonviolence, love, community building, and peaceful conflict resolution. This more positive conception of pacifism aims to transform social and political life. When understood in this way, pacifism is a robust and useful critical social theory. This paper explores the philosophy of pacifism in an attempt to reconceptualize pacifism as a tradition of normative critical theory. The paper argues that pacifism ought to be understood on analogy with other critical theories—such as feminism; that pacifism should be understood in terms of the “pacifist tradition”—along lines familiar from interpretations of the “just war tradition”; and that pacifism should be seen as offering interesting themes and ideas that are worthy of philosophical attention.
58. The Acorn: Volume > 18 > Issue: 1/2
Steven Steyl What Can Virtue Ethics Offer Pacifists?
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Though warfare has been a popular subject of inquiry in Aristotelian virtue ethics since antiquity, pacifism has almost never been afforded sympathetic study. This paper helps to fill that lacuna by asking whether and how secular virtue ethics can provide a theory of pacifism, whether and how it might defeat some common/foreseeable objections, and what additional work needs to be done in order for virtue ethicists to provide a philosophically robust account of pacifism. I begin by translating a pacifist argument from suffering into an argument from the virtue of compassion. Compassionate agents, sensitive as they are to others’ plights, will be highly averse to lethal warfare. In the second section, I argue that cases for pacifism like this one, which are rooted in individual virtues, cannot constitute a complete argument for pacifism because of the commonly held view that the virtues are reciprocal/unified, and that such an argument will therefore require supplementation in order to be action-guiding. The third section elaborates on what I call the impracticality objection. Any convincing account of pacifism will have to respond to this objection, and I argue that virtue ethical pacifism is especially vulnerable to it. In the fourth section, I highlight two avenues available to the virtue ethicist who defends pacifism from the impracticality objection. Neither of these avenues is viable without further research, however, so while I insist that virtue ethical pacifism is not defeated by the impracticality objection, I maintain also that this form of pacifism requires further scholarly work.
features
59. The Acorn: Volume > 18 > Issue: 1/2
Tommy Curry, Anthony Neal, Dwayne A. Tunstall Subjects of Vulnerability: Author Meets Critics: Tommy Curry, Author of The Man-Not, Meets Critics Anthony Neal and Dwayne Tunstall
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
60. The Acorn: Volume > 18 > Issue: 1/2
Duane L. Cady Remembering Mulford Q. Sibley (1912–1989): A Thirty-year Commemoration
view |  rights & permissions | cited by