Cover of The Owl of Minerva
Already a subscriber? - Login here
Not yet a subscriber? - Subscribe here

Browse by:



Displaying: 61-80 of 1392 documents


hegel and constructivism
61. The Owl of Minerva: Volume > 48 > Issue: 1/2
Stuart Toddington The Moral Truth about Normative Constructivism
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Kenneth Westphal provides here a masterful evolutionary account of Normative Constructivism in its classical development, which encompasses Hobbes, Hume, Kant and Rousseau, and culminates in Hegel’s vision of Sittlichkeit. In the process of endorsing the comprehensive moral anthropology of the latter, Westphal rejects the essentialist/objectivist rhetoric of Plato’s Euthyphro and invokes Hume’s alternative to Moral Realism, which is articulated in the view that what might appear “artificial” and “conventional” in our understanding of the rules (norms) of Justice does not necessarily imply that these rules are thus arbitrary. Westphal advocates a metaphysically agnostic Normative Constructivism, which separates our claims to what, on the one hand, is deemed to be morally factual, and on the other, is simply morally relevant. Whilst I acknowledge that this separation of claims is not only possible, but necessary, I argue that it is not, in any critically viable sense, consistent with the rejection of moral objectivism.
62. The Owl of Minerva: Volume > 48 > Issue: 1/2
Kenneth R. Westphal Hegel’s Natural Law Constructivism: Fundamentals of Republicanism
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Replying to my four commentators allows me to clarify some distinctive features and merits of Hegel’s natural law constructivism; how Hegel’s insights have been obscured by common, though inadequate philosophical taxonomies; and how Hegel’s natural law constructivism contributes centrally to moral philosophy today, including ethics, justice, philosophy of law and philosophy of education.
review article
63. The Owl of Minerva: Volume > 48 > Issue: 1/2
Gregory Moss Reading German Idealism: Constructivism and Its Discontents
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Rockmore’s book German Idealism as Constructivism is an ambitious attempt to show that German Idealism is a tradition characterized by the project of perfecting constructivism. On the one hand, Rockmore offers good evidence that this is the case, and it seems indisputable that the German Idealists are preoccupied with this issue. In addition, the text offers deep insights and is particularly strong as concerns the relation of the various Idealists to natural science and the history of science. On the other hand, there is also good evidence that casts some doubt on Rockmore’s thesis. German Idealism as Constructivism may not close the book on this issue, but it certainly contributes to the conversation, and should be taken seriously by any good student of the tradition.
book reviews
64. The Owl of Minerva: Volume > 48 > Issue: 1/2
George R. Lucas, Jr. George L. Kline. On Hegel
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
65. The Owl of Minerva: Volume > 48 > Issue: 1/2
Eric v.d. Luft Aakash Singh Rathore and Rimina Mohapatra. Hegel’s India: A Reinterpretation, with Texts
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
66. The Owl of Minerva: Volume > 48 > Issue: 1/2
New Books
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
67. The Owl of Minerva: Volume > 48 > Issue: 1/2
Recent Dissertations
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
68. The Owl of Minerva: Volume > 47 > Issue: 1/2
Kenneth R. Westphal The Beginning of Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit: Introduction (Einleitung) and Consciousness: Sense Certainty, Perception, Force & Understanding
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
69. The Owl of Minerva: Volume > 47 > Issue: 1/2
David Ciavatta Hegel on the Parallels between Action and the Ontology of Life
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
This paper shows that Hegel’s ontology of living beings provides us with indispensable conceptual resources for making sense of his account of the ontology of human action. For Hegel, living bodies are ontologically distinct in that their objective presence is thoroughly permeated by the self-reflexivity characteristic of subjectivity, and as such they cannot be adequately conceived in terms of categories (mechanistic, chemical, or generally causal categories) that are appropriate to inanimate, “subject-less” objects. It is argued that actions are similar in this regard, and like organic bodies they need to be conceived as self-realizing, self-articulating, dynamic wholes whose various material parts cannot be thought independently of their internal relations and their place in the whole. It is argued, further, that the categories Hegel appeals to in conceiving how organisms develop through stages are useful for making sense of how the objective shape of an action unfolds over time.
70. The Owl of Minerva: Volume > 47 > Issue: 1/2
Douglas Finn Spiritual Consumption: Eating and the Christian Eucharist in Hegel
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
This article seeks to gain a new perspective on Hegel’s Eucharistic theology by reading it through the lens of his philosophy of nature, specifically, his extensive discussion of animal eating, digestion, and excretion. This juxtaposition confirms Walter Jaeschke’s claim that Hegel, in offering a philosophical interpretation of the Eucharist, articulates a sacramental principle governing the whole of reality. In Hegel’s system, the biological process of assimilation serves as a master image of the work of Spirit across a number of natural, cultural, religious, and philosophical phenomena.
71. The Owl of Minerva: Volume > 47 > Issue: 1/2
George di Giovanni A Second Note Regarding the Recent Translation of Hegel's "Greater Logic"
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
72. The Owl of Minerva: Volume > 47 > Issue: 1/2
John Burbidge In Memoriam: Joseph Charles Flay, 1932-2014
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
73. The Owl of Minerva: Volume > 47 > Issue: 1/2
New Books
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
74. The Owl of Minerva: Volume > 47 > Issue: 1/2
Recent Dissertations
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
75. The Owl of Minerva: Volume > 46 > Issue: 1/2
Henry Southgate The Paradox of Irrationalism: The Logical Foundation of Hegel’s Philosophy of the Absurd
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
I resolve a tension in Hegel’s views, which I call the “paradox of irrationalism,” in order to lay the logical foundation of Hegel’s philosophy of the absurd. The paradox is that Hegel both affirms and denies that the world is rational. While critics maintain that this presents a genuine problem for Hegel, I argue Hegel resolves this paradox by showing that reason constitutes itself through the irrational element that it itself grounds. I make my case by investigating the categories of diversity and contingency, which are central to the paradox of irrationalism and Hegel’s account of human agency.
a hegel-marx dialogue for the twenty-first century
76. The Owl of Minerva: Volume > 46 > Issue: 1/2
Philip J. Kain Hegel and the Failure of Civil Society
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
On what might be called a Marxist reading, Hegel’s analysis of civil society accurately recognizes a necessary tendency toward a polarization of classes and the pauperization of the proletariat, a problem for which Hegel, however, has no solution. Indeed, Marxists think there can be no solution short of eliminating civil society. It is not at all clear that this standard reading is correct. The present paper tries to show how it is plausible to understand Hegel as proposing a solution, one that is similar to that of social democrats, and one that could actually work.
77. The Owl of Minerva: Volume > 46 > Issue: 1/2
David Schweickart Marx's Democratic Critique of Capitalism and Its Implications for a Viable Socialism
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
This paper argues that Marx’s critique of capitalism is not, as commonly believed, a critique of the “free market.” I argue that the “market” under capitalism should be understood as a three-fold market—for goods and services, for labor and for capital. I argue that Marx’s critique is essentially a critique of the latter two markets, and not the first. Hence theoretical space opens up for “market socialism.” I proceed to elaborate briefly what specific institutions might comprise an economically viable socialism that would not be vulnerable to Marx’s critique.
78. The Owl of Minerva: Volume > 46 > Issue: 1/2
Philip J. Kain Alienation and Market Socialism: Comments on Schweickart's "Marx's Democratic Critique of Capitalism and Its Implications for a Viable Socialism"
abstract | view |  rights & permissions | cited by
Schweickart and I both discuss market socialism. Neither of us accepts the traditional Marxist view that market economies necessarily produce contradictions that drive them toward collapse. Both of us think the socialist experiments of the twentieth century show that markets cannot successfully be eliminated. Thus, for market socialism, we keep a market and we work to prevent it from producing contradictions, alienation, and collapse. One question that arises here concerns the role of labor unions. Should they (like Hegelian corporations) play a major role in market socialism, or are there respects in which they would obstruct it? There is another important issue that Schweickart should discuss. Market socialism, given its commitment to a market, must face the issue of market generated alienation or fetishism. Can market socialism avoid such problems? And if so how?
79. The Owl of Minerva: Volume > 46 > Issue: 1/2
Philip T. Grier In Memoriam: George Louis Kline; March 3, 1921-October 21, 2014
view |  rights & permissions | cited by
book reviews
80. The Owl of Minerva: Volume > 46 > Issue: 1/2
Robert M. Wallace Giacomo Rinaldi. Absoluter Idealismus und zeitgenössische Philosophie: Bedeutung und Aktualität von Hegels Denken (Absolute Idealism and Contemporary Philosophy: Meaning and Up-to-dateness of Hegel’s Thought)
view |  rights & permissions | cited by